Abstract
Infection, hospitalization and mortality statistics have played a pivotal role in forming social attitudes and support for policy decisions about the 2020-21 SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19) pandemic. This article raises some questions on some of the most widely-used indicators, such as the case fatality rate, derived from these statistics, recommending replacing them with information based on regular stratified statistical sampling, coupled with diagnostic assessment. Some implications for public health policies and pandemic management are developed, opposing individualistic and holistic approaches.
Table of Contents
Introduction
Where Do the Numbers Come From?
Not All Numbers Provide Information
Concluding Remarks
References
1 Introduction
Statistical thinking will one day be as necessary for efficient citizenship as the ability to read and write (Samuel S. Wilks, 1951)
Starting January 2020, public-health authorities, social media and the press reported daily the number of cases, hospitalisations and deaths related to the SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19 thereafter) pandemic. These numbers have been the focus of public, medical and policy attention, and driven public sentiment towards epidemic and its evolution (Craven McGinty, 2020; Infantino, 2021).
Numbers carry an aura of objectivity, and being scientific. Infection, hospitalizations and deaths statistics appear as facts about the consequences and changing status of the pandemic. Monitoring the current statistics is supported by our urgent wishes to control the pandemic, and forecast its future. These numbers make headline news, ranking high in the critical medical and political decisions on pandemic management (Abbasi, 2020; Asselineau, Grolleaum, & Mzoughi, 2021).[1]
The problem is that the reported numbers are poor proxies for the underlying phenomenon (Section 1), and they do not deliver reliable information on it (Section 2). Section 1 discusses how reported numbers on the COVID-19 pandemic do not capture its impact and evolution in a reliable and trustworthy manner. Their relationship with the underlying phenomenon is blurred and potentially misguiding. Section 2 addresses the role of those numbers as guidance for decision-making, discussing how properly-accounted numbers may provide relevant and useful information for pandemic management. An overview of the main argument is given in the concluding section.
2 Where Do the Numbers Come From?
Daily counting of cases, hospitalisations and deaths gathers the hazardous wish to report on the pandemic as it is, that is, to deliver the full and complete picture about its diffusion in real time. Unfortunately, we do not and cannot know how the virus has been spreading. And even if we knew it, we do not and cannot have sufficient social control over its diffusion to track and count all and every case. And even if an almighty authority had such control, we should yet design an appropriate measurement frame of reference to gather those numbers properly.
No such a thing as a case exists, as such. Case detection depends on the healthcare testing for infected people, and the time and conditions of such testing. Even if reliable tests were available promptly and uniformly over territories, not all the population would be tested every day for contagion; therefore, the number of reported cases depends on the ways tests have been performed, to whom and when. It follows that indicators such as the case fatality rate – based upon the ratio between the number of deaths and the number of cases over a certain time window – are misleading and cannot help understanding the ongoing evolution of the underlying epidemic (Brown, 2020).
The number of deceased might appear more solid at the first glance. Nothing seems surer than death and taxes, as the adage goes. But even this number depends on the ways the decease causes are defined and reported. The fact that someone died for medical causes directly related to the COVID-19 disease depends on the healthcare standards which are applicable and the ways these standards have been applied. What if someone died in a car accident while having tested positive for contagion, should this decease be counted? This would imply a broad definition of deceased with the COVID-19 (association). And what if someone died of pneumonia while having tested positive, should this decease be counted? This would imply a narrower definition of deceased due to COVID-19 (causation) including directly related medical complications. Public health authorities have generally chosen to count deceases when a death occurred in a person with a laboratory-confirmed positive COVID-19 test and either: died within 28/60 days of the first specimen date, or COVID-19 was mentioned anywhere on the death certificate (even if not as primary cause), applying indeed a broad definition (Craig, 2021; Heneghan & Oke, 2020).[2] No international standard was developed and enforced.
Similar problems occur with the number of either hospital admissions, or people in hospital beds due to or with COVID-19. Their number may include those who tested positive in hospitals, including those already there for other reasons (likely nosocomial infection), and those who had COVID-19 prior to admission and were admitted for other reasons than COVID-19. This counting depends on hospital infection management procedures, and it is further complicated by the origin of admitted people (which could come from nursing or residential care homes), their ongoing treatments and conditions, the overall length of stay and the number of people discharged from hospital with a diagnosis of COVID-19 (Mahon, Jefferson, & Heneghan, 2020).
Since the number of cases, hospitalisations and deaths depends on both the testing process and the overarching measurement standards, we should be careful when comparing those numbers through time, as well as across different contexts such as countries. Not to forget the fact that measurement standards have been repeatedly amended over time since the pandemic began.
A look at available statistics shows that the relative number of reported cases over the population in various countries differs widely, as does the relative number of reported deaths.[3] For instance, mid-September 2020 (mid-June 2021), around 2% (10%) of US population tested positive, relative to less than 0.5% (7%) in Italy, implying a four-time (+43%) larger contagion in the former country. Does this difference depend on distinctive contagion diffusion patterns, or just the number of tests and the ways those tests were performed and reported?
Moreover, the case-based lethality rate (that is, the ratio of the number of deceased over the number of reported cases, cumulated through the whole pandemic time window, the latter being dependent on data availability) over the population was around 3% (1.8%) in US and 12% (2.99%) in Italy.[4] Was the virus more lethal in the latter, or was this difference resulting from a different way to count for it?
In this context, reports on excess deaths – that is, deaths in excess of previous years or historical patterns – mingle up a combination of deaths that were not properly attributed to COVID-19, plus collateral damage from containment policies (such as undetected medical conditions and postponed medical procedures including screenings).[5] For instance, a statistical survey by the Italy’s Institute of Statistics (ISTAT, 2020a) on mortality over the first trimester 2020 shows that, on total excess deaths (25.354 units), only 54% were COVID-19 diagnosed (13.710 units).
In a nutshell, we have been counting the ongoing pandemic impact by testing disparate people who carry COVID-19 virus in their upper respiratory tract; but this condition does not tell us much about their underlying medical status, neither the reasons for their hospitalisation or death. In fact, mass testing with low viral incidence may certainly lead to an overwhelming number of false positives even though single tests are reliable and properly performed.[6]
Coronaviruses are known to spread rapidly and mutate frequently over time. It is likely that their circulation becomes endemic, notwithstanding pre-existing immune defences, emergent natural immunity from prior infection and vaccination campaigns. For instance, influenza vaccination has been deployed since the 1940s, somewhat protecting vulnerable people without being able to eradicate viral presence and circulation (Montag, 2021). In these circumstances, our current way of counting affords the hazard to keep alerting for the virus prevalence even though its potential danger has diminished and become under control by natural immunities, vaccination and therapies. Imagine if we test for cold all people being admitted to hospitals: We would certainly obtain seasonal waves of persons hospitalised with cold, but this latter circumstance would not add any relevant information about their personal medical condition for public health purposes.
Led by weak and misguiding data-gathering, public health and policy decision-makers enacted draconian measures such as repeated and prolonged lockdowns, disrupting social life. But, at the outset of the pandemic (or at latest about four-six months after it), we had sufficient ex ante knowledge to choose an alternative data-gathering strategy that would have served the societies better. The next section will outline this alternative strategy by addressing the use of numbers for pandemic management and policy.
3 Not All Numbers Provide Information
If numbers of cases, hospitalisations and deaths are poor proxies for knowing about the ongoing pandemic impact, should we abandon our wish to gather reliable information about its diffusion? How could we manage our response without such information? And since guidance is needed, how can we know about it?
Attention paid to the number of cases, hospitalisations and deaths was based on the naïve belief that we can gather the full picture of the ongoing phenomenon in real time, and even forecast it through time and space. As a matter of fact, some scholars have been pursuing a sophisticated version of this very same line of reasoning. They apply models which demand to track individuals and their social interaction, based upon a key parameter called “effective reproduction number” (R t), a pivotal measure of how fast the virus has been spreading. This parameter points to the average number of people who become infected by an infectious person at some point of time. When R t is above 1.0, the virus will continue spreading over the population; when R t is below 1.0, the virus will progressively stop its diffusion. This ‘individualistic’ approach aims to track and control individual behaviour. This focus is consistent with social distancing and social interaction breakdown as policy responses, as well as mass vaccination of the entire population, in view to eradicate virus transmission and circulation.
The problem is that tracking individuals in view to command their social interaction would demand quite an impossible effort, not to mention the violation of liberties and breach of fundamental rights which would be required to perform such effort. In fact, even a less ambitious estimation of that parameter R t would be so dependent on timing and circumstances that it would not provide but poor guidance for decision-making. To be sure, these models are recent scientific advances fostered by computational capabilities of today. But their overarching reasoning seems inappropriate to provide policy guidance, especially in exceptional circumstances.[7]
At a time when computational capabilities were far more limited, social scientists developed alternative approaches to understand and gather information on social phenomena. Among others, Carl Friedrich Gauss did not become one of the founding fathers of social statistics by tracking individuals throughout a certainly untraceable population. He sampled across the former rigorously, in view to infer reliable information on the latter.
Today, publicly available numbers are poorly defined and have been inconsistently collected. Our overwhelming obsession with case counting, hospitalisation alerts and the death toll is simply meaningless, from a Gaussian perspective. Even research studies have used datasets sampled from patients admitted to hospital, people tested for active infection, or people who volunteered to participate. But Gauss would highlight the struggle of interpreting observational evidence from those non-representative samples. According to Griffith et al. (2020), ‘the problem of collider bias (sometimes referred to as selection bias, sampling bias, ascertainment bias, Berkson’s paradox) has major implications for many published studies of COVID-19 and is seldom addressed’.
Instead, what counts would be a reliable estimation of infection diffusion over the whole population, and the correlated risk exposure by certain classes of vulnerable people. This modest approach does not require forecasting the pandemic diffusion in real time, but understanding its featuring patterns as a social phenomenon. At least two statistical indicators would be relevant: the risk for the entire population to develop serious illness and encounter severe outcome, and the lethality rate by relevant classes. By disentangling vulnerable classes, this information would also identify non-vulnerable ones, which do neither get infected (protected by pre-existing immune defences or lack of exposure), nor develop symptoms or serious illness and severe outcome. These indicators may be provided through regular stratified statistical sampling, coupled with diagnostic assessment.
By seeking to track and control individual behaviour, individualistic approaches advocated extreme containment measures such as lockdowns and forced vaccination for all. COVID-19 crisis management has been featured by these extreme containment measures, certainly driven by quite a catastrophic misapplication of the precautionary principle (Bhattacharya, 2021).[8] Notwithstanding national variants in policy-making, a scare and persuade (and mandate) strategy has been enacted and maintained up to date.[9]
Facing ex ante uncertainty about the infection fatality rate, immunities prior and after infection, and the correlates of disease severity, public-health authorities and experts seemed assuming the worst case scenario and acted as if over three out of a hundred infected people will die (Ioannidis, 2021);[10] immunity prior or after infection does not occur; and virtually all the population is potentially exposed and at serious risk of hospitalization and death after infection. However, holistic approaches were able to timely understand the real threat for the population as a whole, along with the factual risks at stake for identifiable vulnerable people. But their claims for a statistical approach to data-gathering remained isolated and unsuccessful (Finley, 2020; Ioannidis, 2020; Kulldorff, 2020; Lipsitch, Swerdlow, & Finelli, 2020, interviewing professor Ioannidis; Fenton, Neil, Osman, & McLachlan, 2020; Lenzer & Brownlee, 2020; Tierney, 2021a).[11] At least since spring 2020, information driven from statistically-sound studies was able to reliably identify both the outstanding risk for all, and the relevant classes of vulnerable people, rejecting the worst suppositions behind the forecasting models and their rationale for excess precaution. For instance, a statistical survey by ISTAT (2020b) run between May and July 2020 showed that people who have encountered COVID-19 and showed that estimated seroprevalence was six times higher than the reported cases.[12] Since April 2020, the UK’s Office for National Statistics (ONS, 2021) started running a representative sample testing survey series based on blood test results for antibodies against COVID-19 taken from a randomly selected sub-sample of individuals aged 16 years and over within the community population (referring here to private residential households, and excluding those in hospitals, care homes and/or other institutional settings). Accordingly, development of serious illness and severe outcome was limited to a tiny share of population, the vast majority of cases being mild or asymptomatic (Jenkins, 2020; Petersen & Phillips, 2020). Similar studies on mortality showed that increased and excess mortalities have been concentrated on the oldest and fragile people, often already beyond median and mean age at the time of death (longer than their cohort’s life expectancy when born), affected by chronic diseases and other comorbidities, and living in healthcare facilities with limited life expectancy.[13]
Statistical surveys of incidence and caused severity may provide reliable information on infection incidence, ongoing immunisation by prior immune defence, infection or vaccination, and the likelihood that infection leads to severe forms involving hospitalisation or death. Actual severity may vary depending on strain virulence; healthcare infection management; population structural conditions (especially age and comorbidities as far as COVID-19 is concerned); and exposure. Since an epidemic and its caused severity may spread in non-linear ways, survey sampling may be disaggregated by areas and repeated regularly over time. In a similar way, statistical inference may help generating reliable information on ongoing hospital infection treatment processes and associated outcomes. Possibly, local networks of healthcare institutions may be actively involved in the data-gathering process, contrary to received procedures which appear to rely only on idiosyncratic mass testing, thus neglecting sufficient clinical and laboratory evidence (including post-mortem examination) and bypassing the medical profession.
This ‘holistic’ approach based upon statistical surveys and inference can generate the relevant and reliable knowledge which is useful for research advancement, policy-making and pandemic management. Public-health authorities may run (and might have run) statistical surveys since the beginning of the pandemic, enabling the scientific community, policy-makers and the citizenry to properly understand its diffusion patterns and emerging risks. Through representative statistical surveys, we can know reliably the factual impact of the ongoing epidemic diffusion over the whole population, and which classes are factually at serious risk. This holistic approach advocates focused protection of vulnerable people, including through voluntary vaccination campaigns, while trusting pre-existing immune defences and emergent natural immunity for non-vulnerable ones.
4 Concluding Remarks
‘Muor giovane colui ch’al cielo è caro’ [Menandro] (Giacomo Leopardi, 1831)
Reviewing the handling of the H1N1 pandemic (the so-called Swine Flu) in 2010, the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe (CE, 2010, par. 1) was
alarmed about the way in which the H1N1 influenza pandemic has been handled, not only by the World Health Organization (WHO), but also by the competent health authorities both at the level of the European Union and at national level. It is particularly troubled by some of the consequences of decisions taken and advice given leading to the distortion of priorities of public health services across Europe, the waste of large sums of public money and unjustified fears about health risks faced by the European public at large.
Since early 2020, a scare-and-persuade (and mandate) strategy has been in place to manage the COVID-19 pandemic.[14] It resulted in disrupting social interaction, breaching social trust, violating fundamental rights, and spending unprecedented amount of resources, mostly unrelated to providing actual healthcare.[15] Relying on mass testing and tracing, this strategy has struggled to control and forecast pandemic diffusion in real time. The entire population is sought to be vaccinated in hope of fully eradicating virus transmission, through discriminatory measures against the unvaccinated in many cases.
Daily numbers of cases, hospitalisations and deaths have been an integral part of that strategy. But numbers are not facts. They result from measurement processes which should be carefully considered (and designed) when interpreting those numbers. Not all numbers provide reliable guidance for decision-making, but some of them do it better than others.
Those daily numbers of cases, hospitalisations and deaths are meaningless when we wish knowing what has been going on with the pandemic diffusion. On the contrary, statistical techniques are available to reliably understand its emerging patterns and implied risks. Strategies based upon such a ‘holistic’ approach would advocate stratified sample testing and focused protection of certain classes of vulnerable people, including their selective vaccination, while relying on mutual trust and the collective emergence of natural immunity for the others (Gupta, 2021). Table 1 provides a dualistic comparison between individualistic and holistic approaches to pandemic management.[16] On the one hand, individualistic approaches aim to track and control individual behaviour (and then advocate for draconian measures such as lockdowns and forced vaccination for all); on the other hand, holistic approaches aim to understand the whole of pandemic as a social phenomenon, then advocating for focused protection of vulnerable people based upon a holistic understanding.
Dualistic overview on alternative approaches to pandemic management.
Individualistic approach | Holistic approach | |
---|---|---|
Approach design | Individual behaviour and tracking | System behaviour and sampling |
Accounting framework | Individual tracing and counting | Regular statistical sampling |
Recommended policies | Preventative lockdowns and mass vaccination for all | Focused protection and selective vaccination of vulnerable people |
Methodological and epistemic stances | Methodological individualism, forecasting purpose | Methodological holism, understanding purpose |
Overall political philosophy | Draconian precautionary measures by authoritarian public health | Informed management and containment measures respectful of individual liberty and responsibility |
Pandemic management and policy require seeking for a balance between individual rights and other people’s protection within the same risk class. The vexata quaestio is whether draconian measures such as repeated and prolonged lockdowns and forced vaccination for all do apply excess precaution through measures which are neither strictly required by the exigencies of the situation (necessity) nor proportional to factual risks (proportionality), resulting in violating the former in the name of the latter. Especially once evidence of the real threats at stake for all and each one exists, pandemic may be managed in alternative and less disruptive ways.[17] And this has been the case since spring 2020 for the COVID-19 pandemic.[18]
Neither individuals nor societies can beat the death, eventually. But we can keep living while doing our best effort to cope with old and new diseases, applying sound public health management and policies which respect fundamental rights.
Acknowledgements
I wish thanking Shyam Sunder and two anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments and suggestions. Usual disclaimer applies.
References
Abbasi, K. (2020). COVID-19 politicisation, “corruption,” and suppression of science. When good science is suppressed by the medical-political complex, people die. BMJ, 371, m4425. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.m4425.Search in Google Scholar
Asselineau, A., Grolleaum, G., & Mzoughi, N. (2021). A good servant but a poor master: The side effects of numbers and metrics. Administration & Society. https://doi.org/10.1177/00953997211043830.Search in Google Scholar
Bhattacharya, J. (2021). On the catastrophic misapplication of the precautionary principle. Collateral Global, Editor’s Note – Week Five 14 June. Retrieved from https://collateralglobal.org/article/editors-note-5/.Search in Google Scholar
Brown, R. B. (2020). Public health lessons learned from biases in coronavirus mortality over estimation. Disaster Medicine and Public Health Preparedness, 12, 1–8. https://doi.org/10.1017/dmp.2020.298.Search in Google Scholar
CDC – Center for Disease Control and Prevention. (2021). COVID-19 vaccine breakthrough infections reported to CDC — United States, January 1–April 30, 2021. CDC COVID-19 Vaccine Breakthrough Case Investigations Team, Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report (MMWR), 70(21). https://doi.org/10.15585/mmwr.mm7021e3.Search in Google Scholar
CE – Council of Europe. (2010). Handling of the H1N1 pandemic: More transparency needed. Parliamentary Assembly Resolution n. 1749. Retrieved from https://pace.coe.int/en/files/17889#trace-3.Search in Google Scholar
CE – Council of Europe. (2021). Covid-19 vaccines: Ethical, legal and practical considerations. Parliamentary Assembly Resolution n. 2361. (5th Sitting). Retrieved from https://pace.coe.int/en/files/29004/html.Search in Google Scholar
CETS – Council of Europe Treaty Series. (1997). Convention on human Rights and biomedicine, European treaty series – ETS No. 164. Oviedo. Retrieved from https://www.coe.int/en/web/conventions/full-list/-/conventions/treaty/012A?module=treaty-detail&treatynum=164.Search in Google Scholar
Chikina, M., & Pegden, W. (2020). Modeling strict age-targeted mitigation strategies for COVID-19. PLoS One, 15(7), e0236237. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0236237.Search in Google Scholar
Chin, V., Ioannidis, J. P. A., Tanner, M. A., & Cripps, S. (2021). Effect estimates of COVID-19 non-pharmaceutical interventions are non-robust and highly model-dependent. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 136, P96–P132. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jclinepi.2021.03.014.Search in Google Scholar
Craig, C. (2021). How covid deaths are over-counted, COVID-19 Assembly February 9. Retrieved from https://www.covid19assembly.org/2021/02/how-covid-deaths-are-over-counted/ .Search in Google Scholar
Craven McGinty, J. (2020). Counting coronavirus cases: Why it’s harder than it might seem. The Wall Street Journal, 17 Apr. Retrieved from https://www.wsj.com/articles/counting-coronavirus-cases-why-its-harder-than-it-might-seem-11587115801.Search in Google Scholar
EU Council. (1990). Council Directive 90/220/EEC of 23 April 1990 on the deliberate release into the environment of genetically modified organisms. OJ L 117, 15–27. (repealed by Directive 2001/18/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 12 March 2001 on the deliberate release into the environment of genetically modified organisms and repealing Council Directive 90/220/EEC). Retrieved from http://data.europa.eu/eli/dir/1990/220/oj .Search in Google Scholar
Fenton, N. E., Neil, M., Osman, M., & McLachlan, S. (2020). COVID-19 infection and death rates: The need to incorporate causal explanations for the data and avoid bias in testing. Journal of Risk Research, 23(7-8), 862–865. https://doi.org/10.1080/13669877.2020.1756381.Search in Google Scholar
Ferguson, N. (2021). How a more resilient America beat a midcentury pandemic. The Wall Street Journal, 30 Apr. Retrieved from https://www.wsj.com/articles/how-a-more-resilient-america-beat-a-midcentury-pandemic-11619794711.Search in Google Scholar
Finley, A. (2020). The bearer of good coronavirus news. The Wall Street Journal, 24 Apr. Retrieved from https://www.wsj.com/articles/the-bearer-of-good-coronavirus-news-11587746176.Search in Google Scholar
Griffith, G. J., Morris, T. T., Tudball, M. J., Herbert, A., Mancano, G., Pike, L., … Hemani, G. (2020). Collider bias undermines our understanding of COVID-19 disease risk and severity. Nature Communications, 11, 5749. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-020-19478-2.Search in Google Scholar
Gupta, S. (2020). We may already have herd immunity – an interview with Professor Sunetra Gupta, Reaction, 21 Jul. Retrieved from https://reaction.life/we-may-already-have-herd-immunity-an-interview-with-professor-sunetra-gupta/?fbclid=IwAR0ucQOKcLEDQNapy0RRFx3TQQ_VhiCANyFWZAzmRoUfHVp8BpablTZxceE .Search in Google Scholar
Gupta, S. (2021). Collateral global – CG mini-lectures: Herd immunity, Collateral Global, 28 May. Retrieved from https://collateralglobal.org/article/mini-lecture-herd-immunity/ .Search in Google Scholar
Heneghan, C., & Oke, J. (2020). Public health England has changed its definition of deaths: The COVID-19 response, 12 Aug. Retrieved from https://www.cebm.net/COVID-19/public-health-england-death-data-revised/ .Search in Google Scholar
Herby, J. (2020). Sweden’s “Dry Tinder” accounts for many Covid-19-deaths. American Institute for Scientific Research – IAER, 9 Nov. Retrieved from https://www.aier.org/article/swedens-dry-tinder-accounts-for-many-covid-19-deaths/.Search in Google Scholar
Horton, R. (2021). Offline: COVID-19 is not a pandemic. The Lancet, 396(10255), P874. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(20)32000-6.Search in Google Scholar
Infantino, M. (2021). Hazards and fallacies of social measurements: Global indicators in the pandemic. International Journal of Law in Context, 17, 168–185. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744552321000264.Search in Google Scholar
Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2020). A fiasco in the making? As the coronavirus pandemic takes hold, we are making decisions without reliable data. STAT, 17 Mar. Retrieved from https://www.statnews.com/2020/03/17/a-fiasco-in-the-making-as-the-coronavirus-pandemic-takes-hold-we-are-making-decisions-without-reliable-data/.Search in Google Scholar
Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2021). Infection fatality rate of COVID-19 inferred from seroprevalence data. Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 99 (1), 19–33F. Preprint at medRxiv, 14 July 2020. https://doi.org/10.1101/2020.05.13.20101253.Search in Google Scholar
ISTAT. (2020a). Impatto dell’epidemia COVID-19 sulla mortalità totale della popolazione residente primo trimestre 2020 [Impact of COVID-19 pandemic on total mortality of resident population over the first trimester 2020], 4 May. Retrieved from https://www.istat.it/it/files/2020/05/Rapporto_Istat_ISS.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
ISTAT. (2020b). Primi risultati dell’indagine di sieroprevalenza sul sars-cov-2 [Preliminary results of seroepidemiological investigation on COVID-19], 3 Aug. Retrieved from https://www.istat.it/it/archivio/256536.Search in Google Scholar
Jenkins, H. W. (2020). The Slow Birth of Covid Realism. Can we now admit that herd immunity and vaccines will work in tandem? Wall Street Journal, 29 Dec. Retrieved from https://www.wsj.com/articles/the-slow-birth-of-covid-realism-11609284003.Search in Google Scholar
Kelly, J. (2020). Covid kills, but do we overestimate the risk? FT Aphaville, The Financial Times, 20 Nov. Retrieved from https://www.ft.com/content/879f2a2b-e366-47ac-b67a-8d1326d40b5e.Search in Google Scholar
Kulldorff, M. (2020). COVID-19 Counter Measures Should be Age Specific. Linkedin, 10 Apr. Retrieved from https://www.linkedin.com/pulse/covid-19-counter-measures-should-age-specific-martin-kulldorff/ .Search in Google Scholar
Lenzer, J., & Brownlee, S. (2020). The COVID Science Wars. Shutting down scientific debate is hurting the public health. Scientific American, 30 Nov. Retrieved from https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/the-covid-science-wars1/.Search in Google Scholar
Leopardi, G. (1831). ‘Amore e Morte’, Canto XXVII. In A. Donati (Ed.), Canti (1917). Bari: Laterza.Search in Google Scholar
Lipsitch, M., Swerdlow, D. L., & Finelli, L. (2020). Defining the epidemiology of covid-19—studies needed. New England Journal of Medecine, 382, 1194–1196. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMp2002125.Search in Google Scholar
Mahon, J., Jefferson, T., & Heneghan, C. (2020). Are COVID-19 patients in hospital or admitted to hospital? The centre for evidence-based medicine (CEBM). Evidence Service to support the COVID-19 response, 13 Apr. Retrieved from https://www.cebm.net/COVID-19/are-COVID-19-patients-in-hospital-or-admitted-to-hospital/ .Search in Google Scholar
Miller, P. (2022). Afterword: Quantifying, mediating and intervening: The R number and the politics of health in the twenty-first century, (Chapter 14). In A, Mennicken R, Salais (Eds.), The new politics of numbers. Utopia, evidence and democracy, Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, (pp. 465–476). https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007%2F978-3-030-78201-6_14.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
Montag, K. (2021). On the efficacy of influenza and COVID-19 vaccines, Multipolar Magazin, 14 Jun. Retrieved from https://multipolar-magazin.de/artikel/efficacy-of-vaccines .Search in Google Scholar
OECD. (2021). Sovereign borrowing outlook for OECD Countries. Paris.Search in Google Scholar
ONS. (2021). COVID-19 Infection Survey: methods and further information, 26 Mar. Retrieved from https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/healthandsocialcare/conditionsanddiseases/methodologies/covid19infectionsurveypilotmethodsandfurtherinformation .Search in Google Scholar
Packalen, M., & Bhattacharya, J. (2021). Lockdown Harms and the Silence of economists, Collateral Global, editorial, 29 Aug. Retrieved from https://collateralglobal.org/article/lockdown-harms-and-the-silence-of-economists/.Search in Google Scholar
Petersen, I., & Phillips, A. (2020). Three quarters of people with SARS-CoV-2 infection are asymptomatic: Analysis of English household survey data. Clinical Epidemiology, 12, 1039–1043. https://doi.org/10.2147/CLEP.S276825.Search in Google Scholar
Rothwell, J., & Desai, S. (2020). Misinformation is distorting COVID policies and behaviors, research report, the Brookings Institution, 22 Dec. Retrieved from https://brook.gs/37DSwwM.Search in Google Scholar
SAGE – Scientific Advisory Group for Emergencies. (2020). Options for increasing adherence to social distancing measures, 22 March 2020. In Paper prepared for the Scientific Advisory Group for Emergencies. SAGE. Retrieved from https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/options-for-increasing-adherence-to-social-distancing-measures-22-march-2020 .Search in Google Scholar
Sunder, S. (2021). How did the U.S. stock market recover from the Covid-19 contagion? Mind & Society, 20, 261–263. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-020-00238-0.Search in Google Scholar
Tierney, J. (2021a). The panic pandemic. Fearmongering from journalists, scientists, and politicians did more harm than the virus. City Journal, Summer 2021. Retrieved from https://www.city-journal.org/panic-pandemic.Search in Google Scholar
Tierney, J. (2021b). Unlearned AIDS lessons for covid. The Wall Street Journal, 3 Oct. Retrieved from https://www.wsj.com/articles/aids-panic-covid-19-coronavirus-pandemic-experts-politicized-fauci-follow-science-11633290650.Search in Google Scholar
Toubiana, L., Mucchielli, L., Chaillot, P., & Bouauda, J. (2021). L’épidémie de Covid-19 a eu un impact relativement faible sur la mortalité en France. IRSAN, 25 Mar. Retrieved from http://recherche.irsan.fr/fr/documentation/index/voir/154-L%E2%80%99%C3%A9pid%C3%A9mie-de-Covid%E2%80%9119-a-eu-un-impact-relativement-faible-sur-la-mortalit%C3%A9-en-France.Search in Google Scholar
UN – United Nations. (1976). International covenant on civil and political rights (ICCPR), adopted and opened for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly resolution 2200A (XXI) of 16 December 1966, entry into force 23 March 1976, in accordance with Article 49. Retrieved from https://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/pages/ccpr.aspx.Search in Google Scholar
UNESCO. (2005). Universal declaration on bioethics and human rights, 19 Oct. Retrieved from http://portal.unesco.org/en/ev.php-URL_ID=31058&URL_DO=DO_TOPIC&URL_SECTION=201.html.Search in Google Scholar
Watson, J., Whiting, P., & Bush, J. (2020). Interpreting a COVID-19 test result. BMJ, 369, m1808. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.m1808.Search in Google Scholar
Wilks, S. S. (1951). Undergraduate statistical education. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 46(253), 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1080/01621459.1951.10500763.Search in Google Scholar
© 2021 CONVIVIUM, association loi de 1901