Abstract
Descartes explicitly states that virtue is sufficient for attaining happiness. In this paper I argue that, within the framework he develops, this is not exactly true: more than virtuous action is needed to secure happiness. I begin by analyzing, in Section 2, the Cartesian notion of virtue in order to show the way in which it closely connects to what, for Descartes, forms the very essence of morality – the correct use of our free will. Section 3, in turn, discusses Descartes’s view of happiness and its relation to the highest good. Thereby is laid the foundation for Section 4, which offers a reconstruction of the argument that virtue leads to happiness. Section 5 concludes the discussion by suggesting how and why Descartes leaves a crucial premise – an intellectual insight that consists of three main elements – unmentioned when he claims that virtue is sufficient for happiness.
1 Introduction
The link between virtue and happiness is one of the most traditional topics in Western moral thought.[1] In line with his rather conspicuous Stoic tendencies,[2] in a letter from 1645 Descartes assures Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia that “virtue is sufficient to make us content in this life” (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 266 f.).[3] In this paper, I examine this claim and argue that, within the framework Descartes develops, this is not exactly true: virtue is almost – but not quite – enough for attaining happiness. To be happy, we need to connect virtuous action to a specific intellectual insight into ourselves and the world at large.
The paper will unfold as follows. Section 2 analyzes the Cartesian notion of virtue by showing how it closely connects to what, for Descartes, forms the very essence of morality – the correct use of our free will. Section 3, in turn, discusses Descartes’s view of happiness and its relation to the highest good. Thereby is laid the foundation for Section 4, which offers a reconstruction of the argument that virtue leads to happiness. Section 5 concludes the discussion by examining the crucial premise Descartes leaves unmentioned when he claims that virtue is sufficient for happiness – a premise that turns out to be integral to the Cartesian world view.
2 Virtue and the Two-Component View of Moral Agency
To be able to discern the nature of Cartesian virtue, I begin by focusing on what Descartes says about the good use of our will, the very source of moral agency.[4] The letter to Christina of 20 November 1647 – so important in summing up much of its author’s moral philosophy as it had developed up to that point – contains a passage in which Descartes expresses his view in exceptionally plain terms:
I do not see that it is possible to dispose it [our will] better than [1] by a firm and constant resolution to carry out to the letter all the things which one judges to be best, and [2] to employ all the powers of one’s mind in finding out what these are. (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83, numbers in brackets added.)
To my knowledge, the first proper formulation of these two features appears in the letter to Elizabeth from 4 August 1645.[5] It is in keeping with the Fourth Meditation maxim, “the perception of the intellect should always precede the determination of the will” (CSM II, 41; AT VII, 60), and runs as follows:
It seems to me that each person can make himself content by himself without any external assistance, provided he respects three conditions[.] […] [1] The first is that he should always try to employ his mind as well as he can to discover what he should or should not do in all the circumstances of life. [2] The second is that he should have a firm and constant resolution to carry out whatever reason recommends without being diverted by his passions or appetites. […] [3] The third is that he should bear in mind that while he thus guides himself as far as he can, by reason, all the good things which he does not possess are one and all entirely outside his power. (CSMK, 257 f.; AT IV, 265, emphases and numbers in brackets added.)
I will discuss the third condition and what Descartes thinks about contentment below; for the present purposes the major point is that, at least from 1645 onward, for Descartes moral agency is about the correct use of our will, which consists of both a cognitive and a conative component. Accordingly, in his last published work he states: “What I call its [the will’s] ‘proper’ weapons are [1] firm and determinate judgements bearing upon the knowledge of good and evil, [2] which the soul has resolved to follow in guiding its conduct.” (Passions, art. 48; CSM I, 347; AT XI, 367, numbers in brackets added.)
The mature Cartesian view of moral agency thus seems to consist of two features. First, we should do our utmost to judge the matter at hand correctly, which requires affirming those perceptions that represent what we, after having reflected the issue appropriately,[6] regard as the good or right course of action. Secondly, we are then to exert our will to make happen what we have judged right. Put together, the view amounts to what I would call the two-component theory of moral action.
One feature of this account can hardly be over-emphasized: it is very sensitive to our finitude. It demands that we, first, find out to the extent we can or as well as it is reasonably expectable of us what is the right thing to do; and then, second, that we strive to act according to our judgment, even though it is not always up to us whether or not this endeavor results in the desired action – and even when it does, whether or not the action has the kind of outcome we were aiming for.[7] Descartes is quite explicit about our cognitive limits, for instance when he says that “we had reason only to do the best that our intellect was able to recognize” (Passions, art. 146; CSM I, 381; AT XI, 440)[8] or that we should examine the issue at hand “as well as we are morally able” (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83 f.). Moreover, the talk of resoluteness and resolve can be taken to refer to our conative restrictions and to indicate that the crux of the second component lies in striving to act in a certain way even though passions and other factors may eventually keep us from acting as we intend. In general, Descartes appears acutely conscious of the fact that he is offering an ethics to finite beings with their limitations – to beings of whom it would be simply inappropriate to demand more than doing the best they can in the circumstances in which they find themselves. It is unfortunate that practical matters do not involve the kind of clarity and distinctness that theoretical ones do,[9] but despite this, we must try our hardest to find out what is right and to make it happen.
Descartes consistently defines virtue by referring to his understanding of moral action, but it is not quite clear whether he takes virtue to equal only one or both of the aforementioned components. In the letter to Elizabeth of 4 August 1645 he states that one
should have a firm and constant resolution to carry out whatever reason recommends without being diverted by his passions or appetites. Virtue, I believe, consists precisely in sticking firmly to this resolution; though I do not know that anyone has ever so described it. (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 265.)[10]
Furthermore, in the pivotal letter to Christina, he explains that “virtue consists only in the resolution and vigour with which we are inclined to do the things we think good” (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83). In these passages he thus equates virtue with the conative component alone; as Svensson 2011, 245 f., points out, this is Descartes’s restrictive sense of virtue. However, in the very same letter to Christina, Descartes also refers to a less restrictive sense:
For the goods of the body and of fortune do not depend absolutely upon us; and those of the soul can all be reduced to two heads, the one being to know, and the other to will, what is good. But knowledge is often beyond our powers; and so there remains only our will, which is absolutely within our disposal. And I do not see that it is possible to dispose it better than by a firm and constant resolution to carry out to the letter all the things which one judges to be best, and to employ all the powers of one’s mind in finding out what these are. This by itself constitutes all the virtues[.] (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83.)
Moreover, Descartes’s two-part treatment of generosity in the Passions (art. 153; CSM I, 384; AT XI, 445 f.) might be taken to suggest a wider sense of virtue.[11]
The textual evidence is thus somewhat mixed. I would estimate that this stems from Descartes’s tendency to treat free will and its correct use as one package;[12] in his ethical thought, he seems generally reluctant to separate free will, its use in forming judgments, and the exertion of will power to carry out what we judge to be best. However, it would make sense to emphasize the second component, because the very French term Descartes uses, vertu, originates from the Latin virtus, which means, among other things, strength and courage. As Rodis-Lewis 1957, 71, asserts: “[V]ertu, ou force d’âme, selon l’étymologie.”[13] Accordingly, the term has a particularly strong link to the conative component of Cartesian moral agency. Based on this, I would argue that, for Descartes, virtue is primarily about exerting ourselves according to our best judgment. Fortunately, I do not think that for our purposes anything of consequence hangs on whether we stress the more or less restrictive sense of virtue, for the way in which Descartes talks about virtue as strength assumes that the cognitive element is already in place: I am unaware of any passage that would even suggest that one could be virtuous without having first judged the best one was able to do, be that judging – strictly speaking – a part of virtuousness or not.
What is particularly important for our purposes is that ultimately, acting virtuously equals acting in accordance with the two-component theory. Descartes thus has a rather uncomplicated view of virtue, alive to our finitude: virtue is very much within our reach, for it only requires that we use our will appropriately. In fact, he explicitly denies that being virtuous would require or presuppose knowledge of specific moral truths; recall: “[K]nowledge is often beyond our powers; and so there remains only our will, which is absolutely within our disposal.” (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83.)[14] One does not have to be a sage to qualify as a virtuous Cartesian agent.
3 Happiness and the Highest Good
To clarify the nature of the Cartesian notion of happiness, it is singularly helpful to examine Descartes’s tripartite distinction between happiness, the highest (or supreme) good, and the final end. In the all-important letter of August 18 of 1645, the passage – as convoluted as it is central – reads as follows:
My first observation is that there is a difference between [1] happiness, [2] the supreme good, and [3] the final end or goal towards which our actions ought to tend. For [1] happiness is not [2] the supreme good, but presupposes it, being the contentment or satisfaction of the mind which results from possessing it. The end of our actions [3], however, can be understood to be one or the other [1 or 2]; for the supreme good is undoubtedly the thing we ought to set ourselves as the goal of all our actions, and the resulting contentment of the mind is also rightly called our end, since it is the attraction which makes us seek the supreme good. (CSMK, 261; AT IV, 275, emphases and numbers in brackets added.)
The first thing to note is that here Descartes explicitly sets happiness apart from the highest good,[15] thereby separating himself from the traditionally powerful eudaimonist tradition.[16] But what does he mean by the two notions? To take happiness first, the passage witnesses Descartes’s consistent view of human happiness (béatitude) as “a perfect contentment of mind and inner satisfaction” (CSMK, 257; AT IV, 264). Evidently, “natural happiness” (CSMK, 264; AT IV, 285) simply consists of “the satisfaction of mind” (CSMK, 268; AT IV, 305).[17]
The Cartesian notion of the supreme or highest good is more complex, but, in the end, quite understandable. The above-quoted passage tells us little about it, but in the 1647 letter to Queen Christina, Descartes analyzes the notion as follows:[18]
[I]t seems to me that [1] the supreme good of all men together is the total or aggregate of all the goods – those of the soul as well as those of the body and of fortune – which can belong to any human being; but that [2] the supreme good of each individual is quite a different thing, and consists only in a firm will to do well and the contentment which this produces. My reason for saying this is that I can discover no other good which seems so great or so entirely within each man’s power. For the goods of the body and of fortune do not depend absolutely upon us; and those of the soul can all be reduced to two heads, the one being to know, and the other to will, what is good. But knowledge is often beyond our powers; and so there remains only our will, which is absolutely within our disposal. And I do not see that it is possible to dispose it better than by a firm and constant resolution to carry out to the letter all the things which one judges to be best, and to employ all the powers of one’s mind in finding out what these are. This by itself constitutes all the virtues; this alone really deserves praise and glory; this alone, finally, produces the greatest and most solid contentment in life. So I conclude that it is this which constitutes the supreme good. (CSMK, 324 f.; AT V, 82 f., emphases and numbers in brackets added.)
I interpret the point as follows: we can talk about the highest good as the overall sum total of all the perfections a human being can have, but in a more salient sense, it refers to judging what is good and acting accordingly in virtue of our free will.[19] The highest good thus amounts to acting morally, as what I have called two-component theory states. It is this Descartes has in mind in an important passage to Christina:
Now free will is in itself the noblest thing we can have, since it makes us in a way equal to God and seems to exempt us from being his subjects; and so its correct use is the greatest of all the goods we possess; indeed there is nothing that is more our own or that matters more to us. (CSMK, 326; AT V, 85.)
Putting together the different elements of this line of argument, the correct use of our free will is the highest good, because it is the only thing that is entirely up to us and as such what is most our own.[20]
To summarize, for Descartes happiness is about having a contented mind, but it is not our highest good: being virtuous – using one’s will as the two-component theory states – is. However, there is a connection between virtue and happiness; as we have seen, Descartes claims (CSMK, 261; AT IV, 275) that happiness can result or follow from virtue.[21] The interpretative challenge is to find out how, exactly, this can come about.
4 From Virtue to Happiness
We are now in a position to reconstruct and assess the way in which Descartes views the link between virtuousness (or moral action) and happiness. So what is his argument for the sufficiency of virtue for happiness? Detailed answers to this question are surprisingly hard to find.[22] To my knowledge the letter to Elizabeth of 4 August 1645 provides Descartes’s only elaborate account on the topic.[23],[24] I have already quoted it because it informs us of what I have dubbed the two-component theory of moral agency, but it should be kept in mind that the context is precisely that of reaching happiness:
It seems to me that each person can make himself content by himself without any external assistance, provided he respects three conditions[.] […] [1] The first is that he should always try to employ his mind as well as he can to discover what he should or should not do in all the circumstances of life. [2] The second is that he should have a firm and constant resolution to carry out whatever reason recommends without being diverted by his passions or appetites. […] [3] The third is that he should bear in mind that while he thus guides himself as far as he can, by reason, all the good things which he does not possess are one and all entirely outside his power. (CSMK, 257 f.; AT IV, 265, emphases and numbers in brackets added.)
Building on this, Descartes ends up claiming that virtue is sufficient for happiness. This is surprising given that, as we have seen, he considers virtue to consist, at most, of what the first two items (instead of all three) of the quoted passage mention. So what is the role of the third condition? Why does Descartes invoke it even though it does not seem to be part of virtue?
Descartes’s argument can be reconstructed as follows. The third condition – according to which we must understand that if we use our will correctly, all the good things we do not attain are outside our power – is based on something the importance of which Descartes is keen to emphasize, namely distinguishing “adequately the things which depend wholly on us from those which do not depend on us at all” (Passions, art. 144; CSM I, 379; AT XI, 436). Now as we have seen, the exercise of our free will is the only thing that is entirely up to us, and so Descartes holds that only things that depend on it are in our power.
But what does this have to do not only with things we consider good but have been unable to attain, but also – and ultimately – with happiness? The passage continues: “In this way he will become accustomed not to desire them. For nothing can impede our contentment except desire and regret or repentance [le desir, & le regret ou le repentir][.]” (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 266, emphases added.)[25] So, the argument consists of two claims: (1) only desire, regret, and repentance can stand in the way of our happiness;[26] and (2) fulfilling the third condition protects us from them so that we will be happy should we also have fulfilled the first two conditions by acting virtuously.
Let us begin unpacking these claims by considering what the letter says about those things that are in our power:
[I]f we always do whatever our reason tells us, even if events show us afterwards that we have gone wrong, we will never have any grounds for repentance, because it was not our own fault. […] [S]ince we have always followed the advice of our reason, we have left undone nothing that was in our power[.] […] It is also not necessary that our reason should be free from error; it is sufficient if our conscience testifies that we have never lacked resolution and virtue to carry out whatever we have judged the best course. (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 266, emphasis added.)
The point is thus put in terms of repentance: we have no reason to repent anything we do provided that we have judged the situation to the best of our abilities and genuinely tried to act accordingly. The reason for this is that in such a situation, even the outcomes of our actions we afterwards find unwelcome are “not our fault.”[27] Thus, as far as things within our power are concerned, the focus is on accountability. Here the already-mentioned emphasis on our finitude makes its presence felt: it is simply a corollary of our finite nature that nothing more than genuinely using our will to the best of our ability could ever be expected or demanded of us, and so it makes no sense to repent our actions if we have done so. In other words, our limitedness has an effect on what we are morally responsible for,[28] and so Descartes argues that no matter what the outcome, if we have done everything as well as we could in the situation in which we found ourselves, our conscience can be clear and thus free of repentance.[29] By the same token, it would be misguided to regret acting virtuously or desire to have acted otherwise. According to Descartes, as far as things that depend on us are concerned, realizing this guards us against the three potential threats to happiness provided that we have done everything within our power by acting virtuously.
What about those things that do not depend on us? Even if we accept that we are not accountable for things outside our power in a way that would make it sensible to repent them, is it not quite understandable, and ordinary, to want or wish things to have gone otherwise? But desiring unrealized things we deem good or regretting that things took place the way they did would, in Descartes’s own account, stand in the way of contentment. The letter does address this issue, albeit in a rather sketchy and convoluted manner: Descartes says that “[w]e do not desire to have, for example, more arms or more tongues than we have, and yet we do desire to have more health or more riches” because “we imagine that the latter, unlike the former can be acquired by our exertions,” even when this is not the case; moreover, we should understand “that sickness and misfortune are no less natural to man than prosperity and health” (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 266). Here, he introduces a line of argument that he presents much more clearly in the Passions. The passage – important enough to be quoted at length – reads as follows:
[W]e should reflect upon the fact that nothing can possibly happen other than as Providence has determined from all eternity. Providence is, so to speak, a fate or immutable necessity, which we must set against Fortune in order to expose the latter as a chimera which arises solely from an error of our intellect. For we can desire only what we consider in some way to be possible; and things which do not depend on us can be considered possible only in so far as they are thought to depend on Fortune – that is to say, in so far as we judge that they may happen and that similar things have happened at other times. But this opinion is based solely on our not knowing all the causes which contribute to each effect. For when a thing we considered to depend on Fortune does not happen, this indicates that one of the causes necessary for its production was absent, and consequently that it was absolutely impossible and that no similar thing has ever happened, i. e. nothing for the production of which a similar cause was also absent. Had we not been ignorant of this beforehand, we should never have considered it possible and consequently we should never have desired it. (Passions, art. 145; CSM I, 380; AT XI, 438, emphases added.)
The ensuing article confirms that “we must recognize that everything is guided by divine Providence, whose eternal decree is infallible and immutable to such an extent that, except for matters it has determined to be dependent on our free will, we must consider everything that affects us to occur of necessity and as it were by fate, so that it would be wrong for us to desire things to happen in any other way” (Passions, art. 146; CSM I, 380; AT XI, 439).
These passages build on a distinction between fortune and providence. The former is merely the result of our cognitive shortcomings, whereas the latter captures the way the world really is and operates. The argument is that we should understand that all those things that do not depend on us have been “determined from all eternity” by “infallible and immutable” providence to be the way they are.[30] Once we realize this, we no longer desire things to be otherwise because “we can desire only what we consider in some way to be possible” and what providence has not determined to be is “absolutely impossible.”[31] The claim is thus that it is a plain mistake to want anything not dependent on us to have been otherwise – it is just as senseless as desiring “to have, for example, more arms or more tongues than we have” (CSMK, 258; AT IV, 266) or “bodies of a material as indestructible as diamond or wings to fly like birds” (CSM I, 26; AT VI, 26).[32] Realizing this, Descartes argues, is enough to subdue our desires and regrets concerning things outside our control that could threaten our peace of mind or happiness.[33]
The third condition thus stands for the point that we are to separate what depends on us from what does not, so that once we have acted virtuously by correctly using our free will – so that our conscience is clear – we can also be at peace with everything that does not depend on us simply because we are not to desire such impossibilities as things determined by providence to have been otherwise. Thus, for Descartes, fulfilling the third condition makes the virtuous agent immune to all potential threats to her happiness.
5 Intellectual Insight
According to the present interpretation, the Cartesian account of the path from virtue to happiness involves – in addition to acting virtuously – an intellectual insight consisting of three key components: (1) the distinction between what is and what is not up to us, (2) the idea that we are not to blame ourselves for anything we do as long as we have genuinely done our best to judge correctly and act accordingly, and (3) the view that things outside our power are determined by providence. The first and the last of these elements stem from an easily locatable source: they are, of course, part and parcel of the Stoic world view. Here is an apt, compact description of how providentialism affected the Stoic take on how to attain a happy life: “Secure in their understanding of the providential structure of the world, which is identical with fate, which in turn is identical with the will of Zeus […], [Stoic] Sages order their lives in accordance with it, assimilating their will to the will of Zeus, living in accordance with nature, and so achieving the smooth flow of life[.]”[34] Descartes clearly found this idea congenial, even though there are, of course, many differences between him and the Stoics.[35]
If all of this is on the right track, it raises the following question: why does Descartes consistently claim that virtue – acting according to the two-component theory – is sufficient for happiness even though it seems clear that, according to his own account, it is not? No answer to this question can avoid being conjectural, at least to some extent. To begin with, it might be suggested that Descartes is, after all, operating with a wider notion of virtue than one might think – a notion that sets strictures to judging well. In a letter to Elizabeth from 15 September 1645 he writes:
In order to be always disposed to judge well, only two things seem to me necessary. One is knowledge of the truth; the other is practice in remembering and assenting to this knowledge whenever the occasion demands. But because nobody except God knows everything perfectly, we have to content ourselves with knowing the truths most useful to us. (CSMK, 265; AT IV, 291.)
The very first truth useful for judging well states that “there is a God on whom all things depend, whose perfections are infinite, whose power is immense and whose decrees are infallible,” which “teaches us to accept calmly all the things which happen to us as expressly sent by God” (CSMK, 265; AT IV, 291). Now this smacks of providentialism, and Descartes connects it to the “useful truth” concerning the nobility and immortality of the soul, which “so detaches our affections from the things of this world that we look upon whatever is in the power of fortune with nothing but scorn” (CSMK, 266; AT IV, 292). These passages offer textual evidence for the suggestion that when judging what to do, these truths are to be taken into account so that they are in a way embedded in being virtuous. However, this interpretation would make Descartes’s conception of virtue intellectualistic in a way that many key passages simply do not indicate. When he talks about employing “all the powers of one’s mind in finding out what” (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83) is the best course of action, or about judging “as well as we are morally able” (CSMK, 325; AT V, 83 f.), he does not in any way even hint that this cognitive component of moral agency would have to contain specific truths about anything; instead, the message is simply that one should try one’s best to judge as well as one can to find out the appropriate course of action in the situation in which one finds oneself.
One might also argue that, within the Cartesian framework, once one has acted virtuously, everything one needs to do to attain happiness is already done; one has only to realize that this is the case. That realization is, it might be continued, in fact a meta-level observation and as such not on a par with something as demanding as judging the best we can and exerting ourselves, against irresolution and passions, to act accordingly. However, meta-level or not, the realization has concrete work to do on the path to happiness, which makes it problematic to overlook its importance in this way.
I would suggest that Descartes downplays the intellectual insight his account involves because he thinks that all of its three main components are innocuous in their ubiquity. That we have control over some things and not others is – one might argue – a platitude nobody can fail to realize. That we are not to blame ourselves if we have done the best we could is, in turn, a piece of worldly wisdom sensitive to our finitude.[36] Finally, providentialism – by far the most substantial component – was in Descartes’s time such a commanding view that virtually everyone endorsed at least some variant of it: it was plainly exceptional not to think that the world is ordered (by God) for the best, or at the very least rationally. In fact, Descartes seems to have changed his mind somewhat on how difficult these things are to realize. In the Discourse, he writes (about providentialism) that “it takes long practice and repeated meditation to become accustomed to seeing everything in this light” (CSM I, 124; AT VI, 26).[37] But in 1645, he writes to Elizabeth that “there are few who cannot recognize it [the right path] well enough when somebody else clearly points it out to them” (CSMK, 259; AT IV, 272), only to state in the Passions that “when we apply ourselves to distinguish Fatality from Fortune in this way, we easily acquire the habit of governing our desires” (art. 146; CSM I, 381; AT XI, 440). Thus, Descartes seems to have come to consider certain views, even the one concerning providence, evident to the extent that little reflection is needed to realize them – it is enough that someone points them out to us. Moreover, it is certainly far from implausible to think that, for Descartes, using one’s will to judge the best one can at the very least increases the likelihood of grasping these crucial truths.[38] Still, even though this answer makes Descartes to a certain extent blind to the philosophical presuppositions of his time, I am inclined to think that it reveals the reason why he overlooks the weightiness of the third condition to the extent that he declares virtue to be sufficient for happiness. After all, none of us can avoid taking for granted at least some things that form the backdrop of our thought; often this results in leaving a premise implicit simply because one considers it so evident.
6 Conclusion
According to the interpretation I have defended in this paper, Descartes’s moral thought forms perhaps a surprisingly unified whole. The highest good equals virtuous action, which involves two components, judging well and striving to act according to one’s judgment. Happiness, in turn, is not the highest good but something that is supposed to follow from it. However, an analysis of Descartes’s argument reveals that securing happiness requires that we have a rather multifaceted intellectual insight into virtuous action. Descartes’s reasons for downplaying this requirement are unclear, but I would like to point out that I do not wish to accuse him of incoherence: I have argued instead that he leaves a key premise implicit because the insight on which happiness (partly) rests appears much more self-evident to him than to us; in this sense, our historical distance allows us to see a philosophical assumption which Descartes feels extremely comfortable operating on. Indeed, all of the three major features of the implicit premise make their presence acutely felt in his theory of the passions: the exercise of virtue, “the supreme remedy against the passions” (Passions, art. 148; CSM I, 381; AT XI, 441), and generosity, “the general remedy for every disorder of the passions” (Passions, art. 161; CSM I, 388; AT XI, 454), both involve not only the distinction between what is and what is not up to us, but also knowledge of the fact that we are to have a clear conscience if we only have correctly used our will. We should thus focus on and derive joy from what is up to us, acknowledging that providence takes care of the rest and that we are to “take little account of all the things outside us that do not depend on our free will” (CSMK, 283; AT IV, 355). The Cartesian sage is certainly not far removed from her Stoic predecessor.[39]
- AT
Adam, C./Tannery, P. (eds.) 1996. Œuvres de Descartes, 12 vols. Paris.
- CSM
Cottingham, J./Stoothoff, R./Murdoch, D. (eds.) 1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 2 vols. Cambridge.
- CSMK
Cottingham, J./Stoothoff, R./Murdoch, D./Kenny, A. (eds.) 1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes III. The Correspondence. Cambridge.
Annas, J. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199228782.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Brennan, T. 2003. “Stoic Moral Psychology”. In The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Ed. B. Inwood. Cambridge, 257–294.10.1017/CCOL052177005X.011Search in Google Scholar
Brown, D. J. 2006. Descartes and the Passionate Mind. Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9780511554513Search in Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2003. “Stoic Determinism”. In The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Ed. B. Inwood. Cambridge, 179–205.10.1017/CCOL052177005X.008Search in Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. 2003. “Stoic Epistemology”. In The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Ed. B. Inwood. Cambridge, 59–84.10.1017/CCOL052177005X.004Search in Google Scholar
Marshall, J. 1998. Descartes’s Moral Theory. Ithaca.10.7591/9781501728532Search in Google Scholar
Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2010. Descartes’ Deontological Turn: Reason, Will, and Virtue in the Later Writings. Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9780511778995Search in Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, G. 1957. La morale de Descartes. Paris.Search in Google Scholar
Rutherford, D. 2013. “Descartes’ Ethics”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy;Search in Google Scholar
Shapiro, L. 1999. “Cartesian Generosity”. In Norms and Modes of Thinking in Descartes. Ed. T. Aho/M. Yrjönsuuri. Helsinki, 249–75.Search in Google Scholar
–. 2008. “Descartes’s Ethics”. In A Companion to Descartes. Ed. J. Broughton/J. Carriero. Oxford, 445–63.10.1002/9780470696439.ch26Search in Google Scholar
Svensson, F. 2011. “Happiness, Well-being, and Their Relation to Virtue in Descartes’ Ethics”. Theoria 77, 238–60.10.1111/j.1755-2567.2011.01101.xSearch in Google Scholar
–. 2015. “Non-Eudaimonism, the Sufficiency of Virtue for Happiness, and Two Senses of the Highest Good in Descartes’s Ethics”. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23, 277–96.10.1080/09608788.2014.982508Search in Google Scholar
© 2020 Viljanen, published by Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.