Skip to content
Licensed Unlicensed Requires Authentication Published by De Gruyter Mouton April 27, 2018

Cognition and recognition

  • Nathan Salmon

    Nathan Salmon is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Barbara, where he has taught since 1984. He graduated from UCLA (B. A. 1973; Ph.D. 1979). Salmon specializes in analytic metaphysics and philosophy of language. In 1984, the Council of Graduate Schools awarded him the Gustave Arlt Award in the Humanities for his book, Reference and Essence (1981). His second book, Frege’s Puzzle (1986), was selected by Five Books as one of the best five books on the philosophy of language.

    EMAIL logo
From the journal Intercultural Pragmatics

Abstract

Expressions are synonymous if they have the same semantic content. Complex expressions are synonymously isomorphic in Alonzo Church’s sense if one is obtainable from the other by a sequence of alphabetic changes of bound variables or replacements of component expressions by syntactically simple synonyms. Synonymous isomorphism provides a very strict criterion for synonymy of sentences. Several eminent philosophers of language hold that synonymous isomorphism is not strict enough. These philosophers hold that ‘Greeks prefer Greeks’ and ‘Greeks prefer Hellenes’ express different propositions even if they are synonymously isomorphic. They hold that the very recurrence (multiple occurrence) of ‘Greeks’ contributes to the proposition expressed something that indicates the very recurrence in question. Kit Fine argues that this thesis, which he labels semantic relationism calls for a radically new conception of semantics. I have argued that the relevant phenomenon is wholly pragmatic, entirely non-semantic. Here I supplement the case with a new argument. No cognition without recognition—or almost none. With this observation, standard Millianism has sufficient resources to confront Frege’s puzzle and related problems without injecting pragmatic phenomena where they do not belong.

About the author

Nathan Salmon

Nathan Salmon is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Barbara, where he has taught since 1984. He graduated from UCLA (B. A. 1973; Ph.D. 1979). Salmon specializes in analytic metaphysics and philosophy of language. In 1984, the Council of Graduate Schools awarded him the Gustave Arlt Award in the Humanities for his book, Reference and Essence (1981). His second book, Frege’s Puzzle (1986), was selected by Five Books as one of the best five books on the philosophy of language.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to my audience at Pragmosophia, an international conference on pragmatics and philosophy, in Palermo, Sicily, and to Teresa Robertson for discussion.

References

Anderson, C. Anthony. 1988. Alonzo Church’s Contributions to Philosophy and Intensional Logic. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 42 (June). 129–171.10.2307/421020Search in Google Scholar

Anderson, C. Anthony. 2001. Alternative (I*): A Criterion of Identity for Intensional Entities. In Anderson & M. Zeleny (eds.), Logic, Meaning and Computation: Essays in Memory of Alonzo Church, 395–427. Boston: Kluwer.10.1007/978-94-010-0526-5_19Search in Google Scholar

Church, Alonzo. 1946. Abstract of ‘A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation’. Journal of Symbolic Logic 11. 31.Search in Google Scholar

Church, Alonzo. 1951. A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation. In Kallen Henle & Langer (eds.), Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of Henry M. Sheffer, 3–24. New York: Liberal Arts Press.Search in Google Scholar

Church, Alonzo. 1973. Outline of a Revised Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation. Noûs 7–8. 24–33; 135–156.10.2307/2216181Search in Google Scholar

Church, Alonzo. 1993. A Revised Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation, Alternative (1). Noûs 27. 141–157.10.2307/2215752Search in Google Scholar

Fine, Kit. 2007. Semantic Relationism. Oxford: Blackwell.10.1002/9780470690826Search in Google Scholar

Kaplan, David. 1990. Words. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 64. 93–119.10.1093/aristoteliansupp/64.1.93Search in Google Scholar

Kripke, Saul. 1976. A Puzzle about Belief. In A. Margalit (ed.), Meaning and Use. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. 239–283.Search in Google Scholar

Kripke, Saul. 1979. Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference. In P. French, T. Uehling & H. Wettstein (eds.), Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 6–27.Search in Google Scholar

Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Putnam, Hilary. 1954. Synonymy and the Analysis of Belief Sentences. Analysis 14. 114–122.10.1093/analys/14.5.114Search in Google Scholar

Richard, Mark. 1983. Direct Reference and Ascriptions of Belief. Journal of Philosophical Logic 12. 425–452.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557950.003.0002Search in Google Scholar

Richard, Mark. 2013. Context and the Attitudes: Meaning in Context, Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557950.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1986a. Frege’s Puzzle. Atascadero, CA.: Ridgeview.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1986b. Reflexivity Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 27(3). 401–429.10.1305/ndjfl/1093636683Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1989a. Illogical Belief. In J. Tomberlin, (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 3: Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, 243–285. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview.10.2307/2214270Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1989b. How to Become a Millian Heir. Noûs 23(2). 211–220.10.2307/2215980Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1990. A Millian Heir Rejects the Wages of Sinn. In C. A. Anderson & J. Owens (eds.), Propositional Attitudes: The Role of Content in Logic, Language, and Mind, 215–247. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1991. The Pragmatic Fallacy. Philosophical Studies 63(1). 83–97.10.1007/BF00375998Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1992. Reflections on Reflexivity. Linguistics and Philosophy 15(1). 53–63.10.1007/BF00635832Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1993a. Analyticity and Apriority. In J. E. Tomberlin, (ed.). Philosophical Perspectives 7: Language and Logic, 125–133. Atascadero, CA.: Ridgeview.10.2307/2214118Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 1993b. Relative and Absolute Apriority. Philosophical Studies 69(1). 83–100.10.1007/BF00989625Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2010. Lambda in Sentences with Designators. The Journal of Philosophy CVII(9). 445–468.10.5840/jphil2010107930Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2012. Recurrence. Philosophical Studies (159). 407–441.10.1007/s11098-011-9773-7Search in Google Scholar

Salmon, Nathan. 2015. Recurrence Again. Philosophical Studies 2(172). 445–457.10.1007/s11098-014-0311-2Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2018-4-27
Published in Print: 2018-4-25

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 22.3.2023 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/ip-2018-0005/html
Scroll Up Arrow