Skip to content
BY-NC-ND 3.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter August 11, 2016

Natural Kinds, Social Constructions, and Ordinary Language

Clarifying the Crisis in the Science of Emotion

  • Cecilea Mun EMAIL logo

Abstract

I argue for the importance of clarifying the distinction between metaphysical, semantic, and meta-semantic concerns in the discourse of what Emotion is. This allows us to see that those involved in the Scientific Emotion Project and the Folk Emotion Project are in fact involved in the same project – the Science of Emotion. It also helps us understand why questions regarding the natural kind status of Emotion, as well as answers to questions regarding the value of ordinary language emotion terms or concepts to emotion research, will not help resolve the observed crisis in the Science of Emotion.

1 Introduction

Is Emotion, as a class or scientific domain, a natural kind or is it a social construction?[1] This is a decisive question for emotion researchers within several disciplines. Some regard Emotion to be a natural kind (e.g. Lazarus and Smith 1990; Ekman 1992; Levenson 1999; Charland 2002; Prinz 2004; Panksepp 2008; Izzard 2009; Scherer 2009; Scarantino and Griffiths 2011). Others regard Emotion to be a social construction (e.g. Averill 1980; Rorty 1980; Armon-Jones 1986; Sarbin 1986; Griffiths 1997; Russell 2009; Barrett 2012). Doing so typically presupposes that an answer to this question will yield testable hypotheses that will help to adjudicate between competing theories of Emotion. It also presupposes that an analysis of our ordinary intuitions about our emotional experiences, as they are reflected in ordinary languages, would somehow illuminate the debate between natural kind theorists and social constructionists about what Emotion is. Such considerations are also implicated in providing an analysis of the state of crisis in the Science of Emotion (see Emotion Review 2010 and 2012).[2]

Emotion researchers also typically fall on one side or the other of the debate on the value of ordinary language emotion terms or concepts to the scientific study of Emotion. Some theorists argue for keeping Scientific Language distinct from Ordinary Language (e.g. Sarbin 1986; Prinz 2004; Panksepp 2008; Russell 2009; Scarantino and Griffiths 2011; Scarantino 2012).[3] Scarantino describes such theorists as being engaged in the “Scientific Emotion Project” (Scarantino 2012, p. 364). Other theorists maintain that the clarification and correction of ordinary folk languages is at least one aim of scientific research (e.g. Averill 1980; Lyons 1980; Armon-Jones 1986; de Sousa 1987; Lazarus and Smith 1990; Ekman 1992; Solomon 1993; Levenson 1999; Wierzbicka 1999; Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Goldie 2000; Nussbaum 2001; Izzard 2009; Scherer 2009; Barrett 2012). Scarantino characterizes such theorists as being involved in the “Folk Emotion Project” (Scarantino 2012, p. 364).

I argue for the importance of clarifying the distinction between the metaphysical, semantic, and meta-semantic concerns regarding what Emotion is. To do so, I first identify the metaphysical, semantic, and meta-semantic perspectives on the question, what is Emotion? Second, by constructing an interdisciplinary taxonomy of theories of Emotion, founded on the intersections of the metaphysical and meta-semantic perspectives, I illustrate how the interactions between the metaphysical and meta-semantic perspectives affect semantic concerns. Third, I take these distinctions into consideration in order to provide an analysis of the observed crisis in the Science of Emotion, and I argue that the proposed interdisciplinary taxonomy of theories of Emotion can help clarify the nature of this crisis: It allows us to see that those involved in the Scientific Emotion Project and the Folk Emotion Project are in fact involved in the same project – the Science of Emotion. It also helps us understand why questions regarding the natural kind status of Emotion, as well as questions regarding the value of ordinary language emotion terms or concepts to the Science of Emotion, will not help resolve the aforementioned crisis.

2 The Metaphysical Perspective

Questions regarding what Emotion is can be divided into at least three levels of analyses: 1) the metaphysical perspective,[4] 2) the semantic perspective, and 3) the meta-semantic perspective.[5] The question of what Emotion is from the metaphysical perspective is concerned with whether Emotion is an objective kind or a subjective kind. These two notions – objective kind and subjective kind – are intended to respectively capture concerns regarding the status of Emotion as a natural kind or a social construction while side stepping various issues regarding what it means for something to be a natural kind or a social construction. Thus the terms ‘objective kind’ and ‘subjective kind’ are not respectively synonymous with the terms ‘natural kind’ and ‘social construction.’ These terms (‘natural kind’ and ‘social construction’), however, may respectively share similar referents or senses with the terms ‘objective kind’ and ‘subjective kind,’ and may also be logically consistent with these terms.[6]

2.1 Objective Kinds

An objective kind is a class of things that have the possibility of being independent of human conceptualizations.[7] It is this possible independence from human conceptualizations that defines an objective kind and its members – as something that is said to be “natural,” and therefore “real,” in contrast with something that is said to be “artificial,” and therefore something “unreal” or “unnatural” – rather than the fact that some sort of material or physical existence is predicated of them. In order for a class of things to have the possibility of being independent of human conceptualizations, and thus be an objective kind, it is necessary for members of that class to be unified in accordance with a feature of the world that has the possibility of being independent of human conceptualizations.

One possible unifying feature is that members of the same class all share some non-arbitrary physical property or properties, including causal properties of efficacy. Such properties unify the members of an objective kind as members of that kind, and make it possible for objective kinds to be what they are without the need of human conceptualizations. For example, Water is an objective kind. All things that are Water are thought to be real and to have non-arbitrary physical properties – being constituted by H2O molecules – that identify them as members of the objective kind Water. Something that is not an objective kind is Chair. Although chairs have physical properties, these properties are arbitrary and do not contribute to identifying any chair as a Chair. What identify a chair as a Chair are not its arbitrary physical properties but rather its structural form and functional properties; but this does not preclude the fact that objective kinds have functional properties. For example, a vertebrate-heart is an objective kind. Not only do all vertebrate-hearts have physical properties that partially identify them as a Vertebrate-heart, they also all share the function of pumping blood throughout the body of creatures with spinal columns.

Furthermore, the physical property that partially identifies vertebrate-hearts as Vertebrate-hearts is intimately related to their functional property. That a vertebrate-heart is made of cardiac muscles partially defines it as a Vertebrate-heart, and allows it to perform the function of pumping blood throughout the body of a creature with a spinal column. Thus the function(s) of objective kinds may also be defining feature(s) of what they are, especially because these function(s) are intimately related to their non-arbitrary physical properties.[8] Although there are such things as artificial vertebrate-hearts, these are not Vertebrate-hearts. They have the function of vertebrate-hearts but fail to have the non-arbitrary physical properties that partially constitute what vertebrate-hearts are. Thus they are not members of the objective kind Vertebrate-heart since they fail to be constituted by cardiac muscles.

2.2 Subjective Kinds

A subjective kind is defined here as a class of things that necessarily depends on human conceptualizations in order to constitute a unified category. Scarantino (2012) might refer to these as ‘ontologically dependent’ categories. Human conceptualizations typically involve the attribution of arbitrary properties, including functional properties, in order to identify things as members of a subjective kind. Thus a subjective kind may have members that are, using Barrett’s terminology, “ontologically objective” or “ontologically subjective” things (Barrett 2012, p. 417). What makes a subjective kind a subjective kind is some arbitrary, stipulated, conventional, or merely operational definition that serves to unify the members into a single class. For example, as mentioned previously, chairs are subjective kinds. What makes a chair a Chair is not its physical constituents, but rather that it has a certain structure (e.g. a seat and legs of some kind) and is conceived of as having the purpose of being sat on. This also does not imply that physical constituents are not necessary for members of subjective kinds to exist. A chair needs to be made of something in order for it to exist, but the physical properties of a chair do not contribute to the chair being identified as a Chair. A chair can be made of steel, plastic, straw, etc., but that it is made of any of these materials does not identify a chair as a Chair. An institution, such as the International Astronomical Union (IAU), is also a subjective kind. Although it is constituted by a collection of people, a mere aggregate of people does not constitute the IAU. All institutions depend on its members having a common purpose, which is necessarily determined by human conceptualizations, and it is around this purpose that the actions of its members are organized. One common purpose shared by members of the IAU is to specify what counts as a Planet.

Subjective kinds may also have physical properties that define them as the kind of thing they are. For example, a planet has physical properties that define it as a Planet, but it is an arbitrary fact – based on human conceptualizations – that these physical properties define what planets are. Thus the fact that Pluto is no longer a planet is not a discovery since it no longer being a Planet was established by fiat, which necessarily involves human conceptualizations. The property of being manufactured or man-made, however, is not necessarily indicative of subjective kinds. For example, diamonds and manufactured diamonds constitute the objective kind category Diamond. They are unified by the non-arbitrary, physical property of carbon atoms bonding into tetrahedral units. They also have functional properties that are intimately related to this physical property; nevertheless, these functional properties do not define them as what they are since the functional properties necessarily depend on human conceptualizations. For example, because of their molecular structure, diamonds have the property of being the hardest things known to exist. Thus they are used for making precision cuts, but this function is not what defines Diamond as an objective kind.

3 The Semantic and Meta-Semantic Perspectives

From the semantic perspective, the question of what Emotion is concerns the meanings of folk emotion terms, especially the term ‘emotion.’ This understanding of what Emotion is from the semantic perspective can be further differentiated into at least two semantic levels: 1) the primary semantic level, on which the meanings of emotion terms are analyzed from the perspective of a speaker as a member of a particular linguistic community, and 2) the meta-semantic level, on which the relations between the meanings of emotion terms within two or more theories or linguistic communities are analyzed. I refer to understanding the meaning of emotion terms from this meta-semantic level as the meta-semantic perspective.

Questions regarding what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective, as it is understood here, approach the question of what Emotion is from the perspective of understanding the value of ordinary language emotion terms or concepts to the Science of Emotion. This is because an answer to the question, what is Emotion, seeks to identify or define the nature of Emotion as an object of study. In doing so, it also seeks to establish a set of meanings for a set of emotion terms, especially for the term ‘emotion.’ It seeks to establish a language of Emotion. Although answers to the question of what Emotion is from a meta-semantic perspective can be understood in terms of matters of degree (see Russell 2010), I provide for the purpose of simplicity an analysis that draws a clear distinction between two ways of answering the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective: One type of answer is that because there is value in ordinary language terms or concepts to the systematic study of Emotion, one aim of emotion research is to clarify or correct the concepts that are associated with ordinary language emotion terms. A second type of answer is that although ordinary language terms and concepts are valuable in some sense, they are not useful in scientific research. Thus one aim of emotion research is to establish a set of concepts for a set of emotion terms that diverge from ordinary language emotions terms.

This difference can be conceptually specified by the different working assumptions about ordinary language that each position assumes, and one way to understand the differing assumptions at work is to ask whether one regards folk emotion terms to be what Hilary Putnam refers to as “trans-theoretical” terms (Putnam 1973, p. 197).[9] A trans-theoretical term, according to Putnam, is defined as a term that has the same referent in different theories. Thus the two possible answers to the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective can be respectively understood in terms of the following two answers: “Yes, folk emotion terms are or ought to be understood as trans-theoretical terms” or “No, folk emotion terms are not or ought not to be understood as trans-theoretical terms.”[10] I refer to those who answer “Yes” as optimists about ordinary language, and I refer to those who answer “No” as pessimists about ordinary language (I use the abbreviated terms optimists and pessimists from this point on).[11]

3.1 Optimists about Ordinary Language

Optimists understand folk emotion terms to be trans-theoretical terms in relation to the language of their theory (e.g. Averill 1980; Lyons 1980; Armon-Jones 1986; de Sousa 1987; Lazarus and Smith 1990; Ekman 1992; Solomon 1993; Levenson 1999; Wierzbicka 1999; Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Goldie 2000; Nussbaum 2001; Izzard 2009; Scherer 2009; Barrett et al. 2015; Ortony and Clore 2015). They understand themselves as referring to the same sorts of things as speakers of ordinary languages. Optimists hold that the concepts associated with folk emotion terms in ordinary languages are approximately correct definite descriptions, especially in the sense that they refer to interestingly unified sets of phenomena. This does not entail that according to optimists there is a one-to-one correspondence between a specific emotion term and a specific physiological state, neurophysiological state, or a unique set of these states. It also does not entail that there is a one-to-one correspondence between a specific emotion term, and a specific thought or behavioral pattern. Nor does it entail that emotion terms have a one-to-one relation with a category of objective kind or a category of subjective kind.

Optimists also accept, either implicitly or explicitly, that there is a reciprocal relation between ordinary languages and scientific languages. Theorizing begins with folk emotion terms, which reflect folk intuitions, and the process of theorizing aims at elucidating, clarifying, and correcting the folk concepts that are associated with folk emotion terms. These clarifications and revisions are not understood as independent theoretical achievements, but as achievements of a society as a whole. Thus optimists typically accept that folk emotion terms in Ordinary Language and the same terms in Scientific Language are associated with the same referents. They liken ordinary folk emotion terms to terms like ‘water,’ where earlier folk concepts may have been imprecise, broad, or even incorrect to a certain extent, yet they were still approximately correct definite descriptions or at least accurately referred. For example, when researchers working with the Aristotelian conception of water eventually discovered that water is H2O, this reconceptualization did not entail a change in reference.[12] Thus, according to the optimistic perspective, when the contemporary concept of water replaced the older Aristotelian concept in academic communities, as well as in the community at large, no linguistic shift would have occurred. The reason being that these terms were understood to be trans-theoretical terms.

3.2 Pessimists about Ordinary Language

Pessimists deny that folk emotion terms are trans-theoretical terms in relation to the language of their theory. According to pessimists, pessimists are not speaking of the same sorts of things as speakers of ordinary languages when pessimists use their emotion terms or redeploy folk emotion terms in the language of their theory. Pessimists typically argue that there is no significant relation between the meanings of folk emotion terms in ordinary languages and the same terms in their theory (e.g. Sarbin 1986; Griffiths 1997; Prinz 2004; Charland 2005; Panksepp 2008; Russell 2009; Scarantino and Griffiths 2011). They often ground this conclusion by arguing that most, if not all, of the concepts associated with ordinary language emotion terms are not approximately correct definite descriptions. They suggest that most, if not all, folk emotion concepts are more incorrect than correct.[13] Pessimists also take the prescriptive stance that scientistic research – research that specifically involve the approaches of only the natural or social sciences – should not rely on the redeployment of folk emotion terms since these terms are typically thought to suffer from reference failure.[14] Accordingly, they suggest a revisionist strategy for scientistic pursuits. They propose that those involved in scientistic pursuits abandon or radically alter the use of folk emotion terms in order to adopt a new scientific language. Given this prescribed disassociation with folk emotion terms and their associated meanings, pessimists hold that folk emotion terms and scientific emotion terms are not or ought not to be understood as trans-theoretical terms. They typically suggest that these two categories of emotion terms are or ought to be understood as polysemous terms.

4 The Meta-Semantic Taxonomy of Theories of Emotion

Given the metaphysical and the meta-semantic perspectives on what Emotion is, we can identify theories of emotion from various disciplines along the intersections of these two perspectives, although I will focus here on philosophical and psychological theories of emotion. The result is a meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of emotion.[15] According to this interdisciplinary taxonomic scheme, many philosophical and psychological theories of Emotion fall within one of the following four categories of theories of Emotion: 1) realism about Emotion, 2) instrumentalism about Emotion, 3) eliminativism about Emotion, and 4) eliminative-realism about Emotion (I abbreviate these categories by dropping the phrase ‘about Emotion’).[16]

4.1 Realism about Emotion

Realists are optimists about ordinary languages (e.g. Lyons 1980; de Sousa 1987; Lazarus and Smith 1990; Ekman 1992; Levenson 1999; Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Goldie 2000; Izzard 2009; Scherer 2009). They answer, “Yes” to the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective. They claim that there is an important relationship between folk emotion terms and scientific emotion terms. More specifically, clarifying the meaning of folk emotion terms is thought to be a central task of emotion research. Scientific emotion terms and concepts are corrected, clarified, or further elucidated versions of folk emotion terms and concepts. Thus realists regard folk emotion concepts to entail some approximately correct definite description, and they regard folk emotion terms to be trans-theoretical terms. The justification for understanding the relationship between Ordinary Language and Scientific Language is that both types of languages share the same referents. From the metaphysical perspective, realists claim that emotions constitute an objective kind. They hold that all emotions are unified by some objective, non-arbitrary, physical property or set of properties (including the property of causal efficacy) that can possibly exist independent of human conceptualizations. These essential elements are typically characterized in terms of innate, biologically given emotional mechanism(s) or system(s), which are thought to be responsible for the cohesion of various elements of an emotional experience. Thus realists generally understand emotions to involve significant causal connections between the psychological (perceptions, thoughts, appraisals, etc.), neurophysiological, feeling, expressive, or behavioral aspects of emotional experiences.

4.2 Instrumentalism about Emotion

Instrumentalists are also optimists about ordinary languages (e.g. Averill 1980; Armon-Jones 1986; Solomon 1993; Nussbaum 2001; Colombetti 2009a,b; Barrett et al. 2015).[17] They also answer, “Yes” to the question of what Emotion is, understood from the meta-semantic perspective. They hold that folk emotion terms are or ought to be understood as trans-theoretical terms. The meanings of folk emotion terms are typically taken to be approximately correct definite descriptions of what emotions are, even if such concepts need further correction, clarification, or refinement. Instrumentalists also ground their emotion terms in the same referents as ordinary language emotion terms. From the metaphysical perspective, instrumentalism denies that emotions constitute an objective kind. They deny that there is some objective, non-arbitrary, physical property, or set of properties that are possibly independent of human conceptualizations, that unify all emotions. What unifies all emotions into a single category, according to instrumentalists, is that they involve a unique class of conceptual categories, such as judgments, appraisals, social roles, social functions, or the like. These conceptual categories are necessarily dependent on human conceptualizations.

4.3 Eliminativism about Emotion

Eliminativism is not a common position among emotion researchers compared to realism and instrumentalism about Emotion (e.g. Sarbin 1986; Russell 2009).[18] This is because theorizing about Emotion has typically been carried out under the opposing assumption of optimism, and eliminativists are pessimists about ordinary languages. Eliminativists answer, “No” to the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective. They understand folk emotion terms to have meanings that are inadequate for the pursuits of scientific research. This understanding of the meanings of folk emotion terms is rooted in two interdependent assumptions: First, it is assumed that the meanings of folk emotion terms entail that Emotion or each species of Emotion (e.g. anger, joy, sorrow, etc.) is an objective kind. Second, it is concluded that folk emotion terms suffer from reference failure because there is no evidence to support positing Emotion or any species of Emotion as an objective kind. From a metaphysical perspective, eliminativists claim that Emotion is a subjective kind. Thus not only is it the case that folk emotion terms fail to refer, but it is not possible for them to refer since eliminativists take folk emotion terms to refer to objective kinds. According to eliminativists, there is no non-arbitrary, physical property that unifies all of our emotional experiences into a single coherent class. Furthermore, given that folk emotion terms have problematic meanings, and Emotion is not an objective kind, eliminativists also propose that the Language of Science be revised so as to eliminate folk emotion terms and concepts from the scientistic discourse on emotion. They do not, however, suggest the elimination of ordinary language emotion terms and concepts for non-scientistic endeavors since they consider the aims of scientistic research to be different from non-scientistic endeavors.

4.4 Eliminative-Realism about Emotion

Eliminative-realism is also an uncommon position compared to realism and instrumentalism (e.g. Griffiths 1997; Prinz 2004; Charland 2005; Panksepp 2008; Scarantino and Griffiths 2011, Scarantino 2012). This can be attributed to the fact that eliminative-realists, like eliminativists, hold that folk emotion terms are not or ought not to be understood as trans-theoretical terms. Thus eliminative-realists also answer “No” to the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective. They are pessimistic about folk emotion terms and concepts. Like eliminativists, eliminative-realists differentiate scientistic research on Emotion from research on folk emotion terms and concepts. They hold that the study of folk emotion terms and concepts does not aim at obtaining truths about objective kinds, which is taken to be the proper aim of scientistic research. They also do not believe that folk concepts are approximately true definite descriptions of what emotions are. They argue that folk emotion terms and concepts entail that Emotion as a class, along with each species of Emotion (e.g. anger, joy, sorrow, etc.), is an objective kind, and they offer evidence to suggest that ‘emotion’ and other emotion terms refer to various disparate kinds. Therefore, eliminative-realists also argue that folk emotion terms suffer from reference failure, and propose that they ought to be eliminated from the languages and conceptual frameworks of scientistic research. From the metaphysical perspective, eliminative-realists, like realists, understand Emotion to be an objective kind. They hold that there is at least one non-arbitrary, physical property that is possibly independent of human conceptualizations that unify all or some emotions into an objective kind. Typically, this physical property is a property of a biologically given mechanism or system of Emotion. This mechanism or system might also be understood in terms of causal relations that are imposed by an Emotion mechanism or system, which explains the cohesion between the psychological (perceptions, thoughts, appraisals, etc.), neurophysiological, feeling, expressive, or behavioral aspects of emotional experiences.[19]

5 Clarifying the Crisis in Emotion Research

Several academics have observed that emotion research is in a state of crisis. For example, Emotion Review (2010 and 2012), a respected journal that aims to foster interdisciplinary research and theorizing on Emotion, recently published two issues with special sections on defining Emotion. In the philosophical literature on Emotion, Charland has characterized similar concerns in terms of “the demarcation problem for emotion” (Charland 2005, p. 84). The general consensus regarding this state of crisis identifies the lack of a consensual definition of Emotion as the significant cause of this crisis (see Mulligan and Scherer 2012; Russell 2012). Some have argued in response to this crisis that the project of scientific research on Emotion ought to be distinguished from scientific research on folk emotion terms and concepts. For example, Scarantino attempts to distinguish scientistic research on emotion (the “Scientific Emotion Project”) from research involving folk emotion terms and concepts (the “Folk Emotion Project”) (Scarantino 2012, p. 364). According to Scarantino, the Scientific Emotion Project “aims to offer a prescriptive definition of the conditions of membership of natural kinds of emotion, natural kinds of anger, and so on” (Scarantino 2012, p. 364). The Folk Emotion Project “aims to offer a descriptive definition of the conditions of membership of traditional emotion categories such as emotion, anger, and so on” (Scarantino 2012, p. 364). In this section, I argue that distinguishing metaphysical concerns regarding what Emotion is (which involve questions about the status of Emotion as an objective kind) from concerns regarding the meta-semantic perspective on what Emotions is (which involve questions regarding the value of ordinary languages of emotion to scientific research on Emotion) can shed more light on the nature of the current crisis in emotion research.

First, given the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion, which was constructed along the intersections of the metaphysical and meta-semantic perspectives on what Emotion is, we can see that Scarantino’s proposal to distinguish the Scientific Emotion Project from the Folk Emotion Project overlooks the fact that many emotion researchers, such as realists and instrumentalists, are not only involved in the Scientific Emotion Project but also understand the Folk Emotion Project to be an integral part of the Scientific Emotion Project. Thus in contrast with Scarantino’s demarcations of the field of emotion research, we can understand that those involved in the Scientific Emotion Project and those involved in the Folk Emotion Project are in fact involved in the same overarching project – the Science of Emotion; and the similarities and differences between these projects can be drawn along the distinctions drawn by the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion. Furthermore, an analysis of the observed crisis in Emotion research through the lenses of the metaphysical and the meta-semantic perspectives on what Emotion is suggest that the crisis may not be rooted in questions about the natural kind status of Emotion. Thus an attempt to resolve the crisis by demarcating concerns regarding Ordinary Language from metaphysical concerns by distinguishing the Scientific Emotion Project from the Folk Emotion Project, as Scarantino suggests, may be problematic.

5.1 The State of Crisis in the Science of Emotion

If it is true that the Science of Emotion is currently facing a crisis, we must be able to clearly identify the source of the problem in order to provide an appropriate solution. A brief survey of the various articles presented in the two special sections of Emotion Review that are dedicated to defining Emotion reveal the following consequences associated with the lack of a consensual definition of Emotion, the questionable nature of Emotion, and the meanings of folk emotion terms:

  1. Fruitless debates

  2. Major impediments to interdisciplinary dialogue and research collaboration

  3. The misplaced tendency to separate cognition from emotion

  4. Unfalsifiable theories

  5. Blindness to cultural differences due to an emphasis on English words

One may argue that disagreements over the status of Emotion as a natural kind is what lies at the heart of these problems. For example, one may argue that an answer to the question of whether or not Emotion is a natural kind would yield testable hypotheses that could adjudicate between competing theories of Emotion. Such an argument, however, not only provides an analysis in terms of ‘natural kinds’ and ‘social constructions,’ which no longer clarify the discourse on Emotion, but also oversimplifies the problem by failing to explicitly distinguish the metaphysical perspective from the meta-semantic perspective. As suggested by the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion, theories of Emotion can be distinguished by their metaphysical perspective as well as their meta-semantic perspective. Thus answers from these two perspectives can logically, conceptually, and metaphysically come apart.

5.2 Clarity Through the Meta-Semantic Taxonomy of Theories of Emotion

In regard to the natural kind status of Emotion, although both the metaphysical and meta-semantic perspectives are ultimately concerns regarding the nature of the referent of the term ‘emotion,’ the meta-semantic taxonomy helps us see that there are in fact at least four possible answers to the question of what Emotion is rather than the two answers that “Emotion is a natural kind” and that “Emotion is a social construction”:

  1. Realism – The ordinary language term ‘emotion’ refers to an objective kind.

  2. Instrumentalism – The ordinary language term ‘emotion’ refers to a subjective kind.

  3. Eliminativism – The scientistic term ‘emotionS’ refers to a subjective kind.[20]

  4. Eliminative-realism – The scientistic term ‘emotionS’ refers to an objective kind.

These four possibilities suggest that the metaphysical and the meta-semantic perspectives are logically and conceptually distinct. Furthermore, even if we grant the possibility of establishing whether or not Emotion is an objective kind or a subjective kind, the attempt to do so fails to recognize that such an answer requires us to presuppose an answer to the question of what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective. It would require us to presuppose whether the appropriate domain for the kind of scientific research that we are concerned with (viz., Emotion) is the domain of ‘emotion’ or ‘emotionS.’ Thus two out of the four competing categories of theories of Emotion would be privileged, albeit circularly, above the other two regardless of the status of Emotion as an objective kind or a subjective kind. Consequently, concerns from the metaphysical perspective are logically and conceptually distinct from the meta-semantic perspective, and vice versa.

Furthermore, concerns regarding what Emotion is from the meta-semantic perspective do not have any necessary metaphysical implications on concerns regarding what Emotion is from the metaphysical perspective. The reason why can be illustrated by the difficulties that arise in emotion research due to either the cultural diversity or cultural universality of Emotion concepts.[21] In order for the cultural diversity of emotion concepts to have any metaphysical import on the status of Emotion as an objective kind, it must be shown that the cultural diversity of emotion concepts is significantly related to concerns regarding the objective kind status of Emotion. In other words, one must prove that one of the following is the case: 1) that the cultural diversity of emotion terms or concepts implies that Emotion is not an objective kind or 2) that the fact that Emotion is an objective kind implies that emotion terms or concepts are not culturally diverse. I respectively refer to these two statements as CDE and OKE:

  • CDE: If emotion terms or concepts were culturally diverse, then Emotion would not be an objective kind.

  • OKE: If Emotion were an objective kind, then emotion terms or concepts would not be culturally diverse.

These two possible relations, and their logical equivalents, exhaust the possible ways in which the cultural diversity of emotion terms or concepts can be logically and conceptually related to the metaphysical status of Emotion as an objective kind. Whether or not the cultural diversity of emotion terms has any metaphysical import on the metaphysical status of Emotion depends on the truth of at least one of these statements. Some pessimists have attempted to argue against optimism by assuming the truth of CDE. I argue here that CDE is false.

One might suggest that nothing we know suggests that either OKE or CDE is false. However, there are analogous cases of culturally diverse terms and concepts being associated with objective kinds. For example, the cultural concept(s) associated with the English folk term ‘cow’ and the cultural concept(s) associated with its cognate in Hindu Sanskrit ‘gow’ or ‘gau’ are very different, yet cows constitute an objective kind (Bovine). Reasoning by analogy, it would follow that CDE would be false: it would be false that if emotion terms or concepts were culturally diverse, then Emotion would not be an objective kind. Furthermore, one might suggest that given this conclusion, it would logically follow that every rational emotion researcher believes in the truth of the proposition that would make statement OKE false. This is because statement CDE is logically equivalent to statement OKE by the logical rule of inference referred to as transportation, which states that statements of the kind “If p, then q” are logically equivalent to statements “If ~q, then ~p.” In other words, statements that have these forms, given the same contents, will have the same truth-values. So if one statement were false, then the other statement would also be false by logical necessity, and vice versa. Thus, given the validity of the rule of transportation and the rational norm of logical consistency, it should follow that everyone who believes that CDE is false ought to also believe that OKE is false, and vice versa. Finally, those who hold some other belief about the truth-values of CDE and OKE would bare the burden of proof to show that their beliefs are either not false or not irrational in some appropriate way, which includes the condition of not being inconsistent or running into vicious circularities.

This argument addresses the lack of metaphysical dependence between the cultural diversity of emotion terms, or concepts, and the objective kind status of Emotion by illustrating how concerns regarding the cultural diversity of emotion terms or concepts have no metaphysical import on what Emotion is. We can draw the same conclusions, mutatis mutandis, about species of Emotion and any other postulated objective kind. Furthermore, we can draw a corollary conclusion about the relationship between conceptual facts and metaphysical facts: Conceptual facts do not entail any metaphysical facts, although the goal of “getting concepts right” might be to ensure that such entailments pertain. As to whether or not metaphysical facts entail any logical or conceptual facts, I leave open to further investigation and arguments. For example, although the cultural diversity of emotion terms or concepts does not have any metaphysical import on what Emotion is, the cultural universality of emotion concepts might (see Wierzbicka 1999; Prinz 2004). Thus the resolution to the crisis in the Science of Emotion may not lie in determining the natural kind status of Emotion nor in demarcating an aspect of the Science of Emotion, specifically the Folk Emotion Project, as being outside its area of concern.

6 The Crisis as a Call for Unification

In light of the foregoing analysis, I offer an alternative understanding of the crisis in the Science of Emotion, and a possible way of resolving at least some of the problems associated with the observed crisis. Although the current call for a universally shared definition of Emotion indicates a state of crisis for the Science of Emotion, I argue that such a call is also an acknowledgment or reiteration of the aim or ultimate purpose of the Science of Emotion. Definitions, of any kind including emotions, have holistic meanings. They are meaningless outside a theory, i.e. a language. A definition of ‘Emotion’ is thus a theory of Emotion, and a theory of Emotion is a language that defines and employs emotion terms. The meta-semantic perspective (pessimism or optimism) defines one aspect of a theory’s framework, and the metaphysical perspective defines another (objective kind or subjective kind). These are some of the presuppositions on which a theory is constructed. Furthermore, theories of Emotion are constructed in order to contribute to the process of building a body of knowledge regarding what Emotion is. This is or ought to be the ultimate aim of the Science of Emotion. We can regard this body of knowledge as the Theory of Emotion: A single, consistent, unified theory that is mutually accepted by experts on Emotion as an account of what Emotion is. Thus the call for a single, mutually agreed upon definition is an affirmation and, perhaps, a recommitment to the ultimate aim of establishing a Theory of Emotion by those involved in the Science of Emotion.

The call for a consensual definition of Emotion may also be the recognition of a need, and a call for, constraints in emotion research. The necessity of constraints for emotion research is evident in complaints about fruitless debates, impediments to interdisciplinary dialogue and research, and unfalsifiable theories. Thus as I understand the Science of Emotion, and all other scientific projects undergoing what some might call a period of crisis, such crises are calls for renewing our commitment to the project of unification as well as a call for a foundation on which such a project can flourish. The meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion contributes to providing such a foundation. It carves out a conceptual space which allows emotion researchers to see that theories from one discipline can and do share essential features, and therefore the same theoretical space, with theories of another discipline. It also provides a way of understanding how seemingly disparate theories from within the same discipline can be similar or different in at least two essential ways.[22]

This taxonomy is not intended to displace the pre-existing taxonomies of theories of Emotion in any discipline. Current intradisciplinary taxonomies of theories of Emotion successfully serve the purposes for which they were established. This is why they remain in use. Nevertheless, these taxonomies reflect the methods, interests, and goals of intradisciplinary research. As such, they are inadequate for serving the purposes of interdisciplinary research, which seeks to go beyond the more narrowly defined methods, aims, and goals of intradisciplinary research. Thus the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion provided here may help resolve at least some of the problems of fruitless debates and major impediments to interdisciplinary dialogue and research collaboration in the Science of Emotion.

Finally, although the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion, as it is presented here, only addresses philosophical and psychological theories of Emotion, it is also able to incorporate theories of Emotion from other disciplines (e.g. linguistics, anthropology, and sociology), as long as these theories are explicit about their metaphysical and meta-semantic perspectives. This is because the metaphysical and meta-semantic concerns, along which the meta-semantic taxonomy of theories of Emotion has been constructed, are fundamental concerns for the Science of Emotion.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the members of the International Society for Research on Emotion (ISRE), the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (SPP), Cheshire Calhoun, Lani Shiota, Bernard Kobes, Jim A. Russell, Lisa F. Barrett, Skramz Geist, and my anonymous referee for the Journal of Social Ontology and the editorial staff of the Journal of Social Ontology. All of your comments, questions, and suggestions helped me make this paper what it is. Finally, I would also like to thank Arizona State University, Clemson University, St. Mary’s College of Maryland, and GateWay Community College, and Cylvia YunJa Mun for their support.

Bibliography

Armon-Jones, Claire (1986): “The Thesis of Social Constructionism”. In: Rom Harré (Ed.): The Social Construction of Emotions. New York: Basil Blackwell, p. 32–56.Search in Google Scholar

Averill, J. R. (1980): “A Constructivist View of Emotion”. In: Robert Plutchik and Henry Kellerman (Eds.): Theories of Emotion: Emotion, Theory, Research, and Experience. New York: Academic Press.10.1016/B978-0-12-558701-3.50018-1Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F. (2006): “Are Emotions Natural Kinds”. In: Perspectives on Psychological Science 1. No. 1, p. 28–58.10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00003.xSearch in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F. (2007a): “The Experience of Emotion”. In: Annual Review of Psychology 58, p. 373–403.10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085709Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F. (2007b): “The Science of Emotion: What People Believe, What the Evidence Shows, and Where to Go From Here”. In: James J. Blascovich and Christine R. Hartel (Eds.): Human Behavior in Military Context. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press, p. 189–216.Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F. (2012): “Emotions Are Real”. In: American Psychological Association 12. No. 3, p. 413–429.10.1037/a0027555Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F. (2013): “Psychological Construction: The Darwinian Approach to the Science of Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 5. No. 4, p. 379–389.10.1177/1754073913489753Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F., Maria Gendron, and Yang-Ming Huang (2009): “Do Discrete Emotions Exists”. In: Philosophical Psychology 22. No. 4, p. 427–437.10.1080/09515080903153634Search in Google Scholar

Barrett, Lisa F., Christine D. Wilson-Mendenhal, and Lawrence W. Barsalou. (2015): “The Conceptual Act Theory: A Roadmap”. In: Lisa F. Barrett and James A. Russell (Eds.): The Psychological Construction of Emotion. New York: Guilford Press, p. 83–110.Search in Google Scholar

Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron (2000): The Subtlety of Emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6548.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Carnap, Rudolf (1938): “Empiricism and the Language of Science”. In: Synthese 3. No. 12, p. 33–35.Search in Google Scholar

Carnap, Rudolf (1955): “Meaning and Synonymy in Natural Languages”. In: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 6. No. 3, p. 33–47.10.1515/9783111546216-004Search in Google Scholar

Charland, Louis C. (2002): “The Natural Kind Status of Emotion”. In: British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53, p. 511–37.10.1093/bjps/53.4.511Search in Google Scholar

Charland, Louis C. (2005): “The Heat of Emotion: Valence and the Demarcation Problem”. In: Journal of Consciousness Studies 12, No. 8–10, p. 82–102.Search in Google Scholar

Colombetti, Giovanna (2009a): “From Affect Programs to Dynamical Discrete Emotions”. In: Philosophical Psychology 22. No. 4, p. 407–425.10.1080/09515080903153600Search in Google Scholar

Colombetti, Giovanna (2009b): “What Language Does to Feelings”. In: Journal of Consciousness Studies 16, p. 4–26 (post-print).Search in Google Scholar

de Sousa, Ronald (1987): The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/5760.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

de Sousa, Ronald (1992): “Emotion”. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.): The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/emotion/.Search in Google Scholar

Ekman, Paul (1992): “An Argument for Basic Emotions”. In: Cognition and Emotion 6. No. 3/4, p. 169–200.10.1080/02699939208411068Search in Google Scholar

Ekman, Paul and Daniel Cordaro (2011): “What is Meant by Calling Emotions Basic”. In: Emotion Review 3, p. 364–370.10.1177/1754073911410740Search in Google Scholar

Goldie, Peter (2000): The Emotions. New York: Clarendon Press.Search in Google Scholar

Greenwood, John D. (1991): The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science. New York: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Griffiths, Paul E. (1997): What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226308760.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Harris, Christine (Ed.) (2010): “Special Section: On Defining Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 2. No. 4, p. 315–402.Search in Google Scholar

Harris, Christine (Ed.) (2012): “Special Section: On Defining Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 4. No. 4, p. 337–443.10.1177/1754073912445857Search in Google Scholar

Izzard, Carroll (2009): “Emotion Theory and Research: Highlights, Unanswered Questions, and Emerging Issues”. In: Annual Review of Psychology 60, p. 1–25.10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163539Search in Google Scholar

Ladyman, James (2011): “The Scientistic Stance: The Empirical and Materialist Stances Reconciled”. In: Synthese 178, p. 87–98.10.1007/s11229-009-9513-0Search in Google Scholar

Lazarus, Richard S. and Craig A. Smith (1990): “Emotion and Adaptation”. In: Lawrence A. Pervin (Ed.): Handbook of Personality. New York: Guilford Press.Search in Google Scholar

Levenson, Robert W. (1999): “The Interpersonal Functions of Emotion”. In: Cognition and Emotion 13. No. 5, p. 481–504.10.1080/026999399379159Search in Google Scholar

Lyons, William E. (1980): Emotion. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511609244Search in Google Scholar

Mulligan, Kevin and Klaus Scherer (2012): “Introduction to the Special Selection: On Defining Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 4. No. 4, p. 345–357.10.1177/1754073912445818Search in Google Scholar

Needham, Paul (2002): “The Discovery that Water is H2O”. In: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16. No. 3, p. 205–226.10.1080/0269859022000013300Search in Google Scholar

Nussbaum, Martha C. (2001): Upheavals of Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511840715Search in Google Scholar

Ortony, Andrew and Gerald Clore (2015): “Can An Appraisal Model Be Compatible with Psychological Constructionism”. In: Lisa F. Barrett. and James A. Russell (Eds.): The Psychological Construction of Emotion. New York: Guilford Press, p. 503–333.Search in Google Scholar

Panksepp, Jaak (2008): “Carving ‘Natural’ Emotions: ‘Kindly’ from Bottom-up but not Top-down”. In: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 28. No. 2, p. 395–422.10.1037/h0092065Search in Google Scholar

Prinz, Jesse (2004): Gut Reactions. New York: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Putnam, Hilary (1975; reprint 1989): “Explanation and Reference”. In: Hilary Putnam (Ed.): Mind, Language, and Reality. Vol. 2. New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 196–214. Citations refer to the reprint edition.10.1017/CBO9780511625251.013Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. (1951): “Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism”. In: The Philosophical Review 60. No. 1, p. 20–43.10.2307/2181906Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. (1957): “The Scope and Language of Science”. In: The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 8. No. 29, p. 1–17.10.2307/j.ctv1pncnhw.13Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. (1960a): “Carnap and Logical Truth”. In: Synthese 12. No. 4, p. 350–374.10.1007/BF00485423Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. (1960b): Word and Object. Cambridge: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9636.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. (1992): Pursuit of Truth (revised edition). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Rorty, Amélie O. (1980). “Explaining Emotions”. In: Amélie O. Rorty (Ed.): Explaining Emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press, p. 103–126.Search in Google Scholar

Russell, James A. (2009): “Emotion, Core Affect, and Psychological Construction”. In: Cognition and Emotion 23, p. 1259–1283.10.1080/02699930902809375Search in Google Scholar

Russell, James A. (2010): “Descriptive and Prescriptive Definitions of Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 2, p. 377–378.10.1177/1754073910374667Search in Google Scholar

Russell, James A. (2012): “Introduction to the Special Selection: On Defining Emotion”. In: Emotion Review 4. No. 4, p. 337.10.1177/1754073912445857Search in Google Scholar

Sarbin, Theodore R. (1986): “Emotion and Act: Roles and Rhetoric”. In: Rom Harré (Ed.): The Social Construction of Emotions. New York: Blackwell, p. 83–97.Search in Google Scholar

Scarantino, Andrea (2012): “How to Define Emotions Scientifically”. In: Emotion Review 4, p. 358–368.10.1177/1754073912445810Search in Google Scholar

Scarantino, Andrea and Paul Griffiths (2011): “Don’t Give Up on Basic Emotions”. In: Emotion Review 3. No. 4, p. 444–454.10.1177/1754073911410745Search in Google Scholar

Scherer, Klaus (2009): “Emotion as Emergent Processes: They Require a Dynamic Computational Architecture”. In: Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364, p. 3459–3474.10.1098/rstb.2009.0141Search in Google Scholar

Solomon, Robert C. (1993): The Passions. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Search in Google Scholar

Wierzbicka, Anna (1999): “Emotional Universals”. In: Language Design 2, p. 23–69.10.1017/CBO9780511521256.007Search in Google Scholar

Wierzbicka, Anna (2009): “Overcoming Anglocentrism in Emotion Research”. In: Emotion Review 1. No. 1, p. 21–23.10.1177/1754073908097179Search in Google Scholar

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1997): Philosophical Investigations. Malden: Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Zachar, Peter (2006): “The Classification of Emotion and Scientific Realism”. In: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 26, p. 120–138.10.1037/h0091270Search in Google Scholar

Zachar, Peter (2008): “A Triptych on Affective Science: Response to Commentary”. In: Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 28. No. 2, p. 444–453.10.1037/h0092068Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2016-8-11
Published in Print: 2016-8-1

©2016, Cecilea Mun, published by De Gruyter.

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.

Downloaded on 4.12.2023 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/jso-2015-0051/html
Scroll to top button