Abstract
Recent scholarly attention to ‘legitimate expectations’ and their role in legal transitions has yielded widely varying principles for distinguishing between legitimate and non-legitimate expectations. This article suggests that methodological reflection may facilitate substantive progress in the debate. Specifically, it proposes and defends the use of a wide reflective equilibrium methodology for constructing, justifying and critiquing theories of legitimate expectations and other kinds of normative theories about legal transitions. The methodology involves three levels of analysis — normative principles, their theoretical antecedents, and considered judgements about their implications in specific cases — and iteration between these three levels in an effort to ensure coherence. The payoffs from applying this methodology to the legitimate expectations debate are illustrated through a discussion of examples from the existing literature. Some proposed innovations to the methodology, including the incorporation of insights from the ideal/non-ideal theory debate, are likely to be of wider interest to political theorists.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to Eric Brandstedt, Kai Spiekermann, Joe Mazor, two anonymous reviewers and the guest editors of the present special issue for helpful comments. An earlier version of this article was presented at the conference on Justice and Legitimate Expectations, held in Graz during June 2016, at which I benefited from discussions with the conference participants, among whom I wish especially to thank Sabine Hohl, who formally responded to my presentation, and Alex Brown.
References
Bell, D. (2016). ‘Communitarianism’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/communitarianism/ (accessed on August 16, 2017).10.1002/9781118785317.weom020091Search in Google Scholar
Bovens, L. (2011). ‘A Lockean Defense of Grandfathering Emission Rights’, in D.G. Arnold (ed.). The Ethics of Global Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 124–144.10.1017/CBO9780511732294.007Search in Google Scholar
Bratman, M.E. (1987). Intention, Plans and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press).Search in Google Scholar
Brown, A. (2011). ‘Justifying Compensation for Frustrated Legitimate Expectations’, Law and Philosophy 30 (6): 699–728.10.1007/s10982-011-9108-zSearch in Google Scholar
Brown, A. (2012). ‘Rawls, Buchanan, and the Legal Doctrine of Legitimate Expectations’, Social Theory and Practice 38 (4): 617–645.10.5840/soctheorpract201238434Search in Google Scholar
Brown, A. (2017). ‘A Theory of Legitimate Expectations’. Journal of Political Philosophy. doi:10.1111/jopp.12135Search in Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (1975). ‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations’, Philosophical Studies 28: 419–425.10.1007/BF00372903Search in Google Scholar
Bullard, N. (2014). Fossil Fuel Divestment: A $5 Trillion Challenge (Bloomberg New Energy Finance White Paper). https://data.bloomberglp.com/bnef/sites/4/2014/08/BNEF_DOC_2014-08-25-Fossil-Fuel-Divestment.pdf (accessed on September 15, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
Carbon Tracker Initiative. (2011). Unburnable Carbon – are the World’s Financial Markets Carrying a Carbon Bubble? (Carbon Tracker Initiative). https://www.carbontracker.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/09/Unburnable-Carbon-Full-rev2-1.pdf (accessed on September 15, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
Carter, I. (2011). ‘Respect and the Basis of Equality’, Ethics 121 (3): 538–571.10.1086/658897Search in Google Scholar
Cohen, J. (1989). ‘Democratic Equality’, Ethics 99 (4): 727–751.10.1086/293119Search in Google Scholar
Constant, B. (1819). ‘The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns’, available at: http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/constant1819.pdf (accessed on August 16, 2017).10.7312/blau17412-021Search in Google Scholar
Crouch, C. (2011). The Strange Non-Death of Neo-Liberalism (Cambridge: Polity Press).Search in Google Scholar
Daniels, N. (1996). Justice and Justification: Reflective Equilibrium in Theory and Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).10.1017/CBO9780511624988Search in Google Scholar
Daniels, N. (2016). ‘Reflective Equilibrium’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://stanford.library.sydney.edu.au/entries/reflective-equilibrium/ (accessed on August 16, 2017).10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/01063-9Search in Google Scholar
DePaul, M.R. (1987). ‘Two Conceptions of Coherence Methods in Ethics’, Mind 96: 463–481.10.1093/mind/XCVI.384.463Search in Google Scholar
DePaul, M.R. (1993). Balance and Refinement: Beyond Coherence Methods of Moral Enquiry (London: Routledge).Search in Google Scholar
Epstein, R.A. (1985). Takings: Private Property and the Power of Eminent Domain (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press).Search in Google Scholar
Farrelly, C. (2007). ‘Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation’, Political Studies 55 (4): 844–864.10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00656.xSearch in Google Scholar
Freeman, S. (2007). Rawls (London: Routledge).10.4324/9780203086605Search in Google Scholar
Fried, B.H. (2003). ‘Ex Ante/Ex Post’, Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 13: 123–160.10.2139/ssrn.390462Search in Google Scholar
Gaus, G., Courtland, S.D., and Schmidtz, D. (2015). ‘Liberalism’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://stanford.library.sydney.edu.au/entries/liberalism/ (accessed on August 16, 2017).10.4324/9780203092231-28Search in Google Scholar
Goodin, R.E. (1995). Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).10.1017/CBO9780511625053Search in Google Scholar
Heede, R. (2014). ‘Tracing Anthropogenic Carbon Dioxide and Methane Emissions to Fossil Fuel and Cement Producers, 1854–2010’, Climatic Change 122 (1–2): 229–241.10.1007/s10584-013-0986-ySearch in Google Scholar
IPCC. (2014). ‘Summary for Policymakers’, in O. Edenhofer, et al (eds.). Climate Change 2014: Mitigation of Climate Change. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 1–30.Search in Google Scholar
Kanbur, R. (2003). ‘Development Economics and the Compensation Principle’, International Social Science Journal 55 (175): 27–35.10.1111/1468-2451.5501003Search in Google Scholar
Knight, C. (2006). ‘The Method of Reflective Equilibrium: Wide, Radical, Fallible, Plausible’, Philosophical Papers 35 (2): 205–229.10.1080/05568640609485180Search in Google Scholar
Knight, C. (2017). ‘Reflective Equilibrium’, in A. Blau (ed.). Methods in Analytical Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 46–64.10.1017/9781316162576.005Search in Google Scholar
Kymlicka, W. (1989). Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Search in Google Scholar
Leydet, D. (2015). ‘Citizenship’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://stanford.library.usyd.edu.au/entries/citizenship/ (accessed on August 16, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
List, C. and Valentini, L. (2016). ‘The Methodology of Political Theory’, in H. Cappelen, T. Szabó Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 525–550.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.10Search in Google Scholar
Meyer, L. and Sanklecha, P. (2011). ‘Individual Expectations and Climate Justice’, Analyse & Kritik 33 (2): 449–471.10.1515/auk-2011-0208Search in Google Scholar
Meyer, L. and Sanklecha, P. (2014). ‘How Legitimate Expectations Matter in Climate Justice’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics 13 (4): 369–393.10.1177/1470594X14541522Search in Google Scholar
Mills, C.W. (2000). ‘“Ideal Theory” as Ideology’, Hypatia 20 (3): 165–184.Search in Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. (1987). ‘Abstraction, Idealization and Ideology in Ethics’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 22: 55–69.10.1017/S0957042X00003667Search in Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. (1996). Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).10.1017/CBO9780511621239Search in Google Scholar
Ramsay, M. (1997). What’s Wrong with Liberalism? A Radical Critique of Liberal Political Philosophy (London: Leicester University Press).Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press).10.4159/9780674042605Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1974). ‘The Independence of Moral Theory’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48: 5–22.10.2307/3129858Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press).Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised edition (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press).10.4159/9780674042582Search in Google Scholar
Ripstein, A. (1987). ‘Foundationalism in Political Theory’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 16 (2): 115–137.Search in Google Scholar
Robeyns, I. (2008). ‘Ideal Theory in Theory and Practice’, Social Theory and Practice 34 (3): 341–362.10.5840/soctheorpract200834321Search in Google Scholar
Sen, A. (1979). ‘Equality of What?’, The Tanner Lecture on Human Values (Stanford University) 22 May. http://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/s/sen80.pdf (accessed on September 15, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
Shavell, S. (2008). ‘On Optimal Legal Change, Past Behavior, and Grandfathering’, The Journal of Legal Studies 37 (1): 37–85.10.1086/588264Search in Google Scholar
Shaviro, D. (2000). When Rules Change: An Economic and Political Analysis of Transition Relief and Retroactivity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Search in Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. (1962). The Methods of Ethics: Seventh edition (London: MacMillan & Co).10.1007/978-1-349-81786-3Search in Google Scholar
Stern, N. (2015). Why are We Waiting? the Logic, Urgency, and Promise of Tackling Climate Change (Cambridge, MA.: The MIT Press).10.7551/mitpress/10408.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Search in Google Scholar
Timmons, M. (2002). Moral Theory: An Introduction: First edition (Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield).Search in Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2009). ‘On the Apparent Paradox of Ideal Theory’, Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (3): 332–355.10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00317.xSearch in Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2016). ‘The Rule of Law’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://stanford.library.sydney.edu.au/entries/rule-of-law/ (accessed on August 16, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
Willett, C., Anderson, E., and Meyers, D. (2015). ‘Feminist Perspectives on the Self’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-self/(accessed on August 16, 2017).Search in Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1973). ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’, in J.J.C. Smart and B. Williams (eds.). Utilitarianism For & Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 80–150.10.1017/CBO9780511840852Search in Google Scholar
Wonnell, C.T. (2003). ‘The Noncompensation Thesis and Its Critics: A Review of This Symposium’s Challenges to the Argument for Not Compensating Victims of Legal Transitions’, Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 13: 293–311.Search in Google Scholar
© 2017 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston