Abstract
Robert Hooke’s theory of gravitation is a promising case study for probing the fruitfulness of Menachem Fisch’s insistence on the centrality of trading zone mediators for rational change in the history of science and mathematics. In 1679, Hooke proposed an innovative explanation of planetary motions to Newton’s attention. Until the correspondence with Hooke, Newton had embraced planetary models, whereby planets move around the Sun because of the action of an ether filling the interplanetary space. Hooke’s model, instead, consisted in the idea that planets move in the void space under the influence of a gravitational attraction directed toward the sun. There is no doubt that the correspondence with Hooke allowed Newton to conceive a new explanation for planetary motions. This explanation was proposed by Hooke as a hypothesis that needed mathematical development and experimental confirmation. Hooke formulated his new model in a mathematical language which overlapped but not coincided with Newton’s who developed Hooke’s hypothetical model into the theory of universal gravitation as published in the Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687). The nature of Hooke’s contributions to mathematized natural philosophy, however, was contested during his own lifetime and gave rise to negative evaluations until the last century. Hooke has been often contrasted to Newton as a practitioner rather than as a “scientist” and unfavorably compared to the eminent Lucasian Professor. Hooke’s correspondence with Newton seems to me an example of the phenomenon, discussed by Fisch in his philosophical works, of the invisibility in official historiography of “trading zone mediators,” namely, of those actors that play a role, crucial but not easily recognized, in promoting rational scientific framework change.
Current historiography of science – diverse, wide-ranging, and richly reflective as it has become in recent decades – passes such figures [ambivatated members of sufficient standing and voice to he heard and adhered to] over in near silence. Historians of science show little awareness of their existence and hardly any interest in exposing and analyzing the sources of their ambivalence and its effect on their peers. Attempting to tell their story raises two related questions: that of their visibility, and that of the nature of their impact.
(Fisch, Creatively Undecided, 120)
1 Introduction
Fisch’s Creatively Undecided (2017) and Fisch and Benbaji’s The View from Within (2011) offer a highly innovative and philosophically technical argument in favor of rational normative change. A basic element of Fisch’s argument is the importance of an environment of normative critics and the centrality of ambivalence. The environment is identified with a modified version of Peter Galison’s “trading zone”: an environment where the adoption of an “inter-language” (a pidgin designed to combine simplified versions of the parties’ professional jargons) enables the mutual engagement of two complex sociological and symbolic systems. Note: not only to trade, as in Galison’s Image and Logic (1997) but to fight, discuss, destabilize. Trading zones, construed à la Fisch, entail the necessity to make – as far as possible – tacit knowledge explicit and in general to discuss normative assumptions creating ambivalence, self-criticism, and potential normative change. [1] Further, we are told that the destabilizing effect of ambivalence is the work of individuals: “trading zones are only visited by individuals, never by whole communities.” [2] Fisch makes it clear that the virtuous destabilizing effect that induces rational framework replacement is the contribution – not recognized by a historiography focused on achievement rather than on creative indecision – of those practitioners he calls, with a happy neologism, “ambivalated individuals.” [3] These individuals remain largely “invisible” in official historiography. Fisch’s work is thus an invitation for the historian of science and mathematics to provide alternative narratives; narratives in which the role of “trading zone mediators” in triggering rational framework change is recognized. Fisch has carried out some wonderful research aimed at showing how his philosophical account can be applied to a somewhat invisible and “creatively undecided” figure in British algebra, George Peacock. [4]
The goal of this article is to probe the fruitfulness of Fisch’s account of “ambivalated trading zone mediators” for the historian of seventeenth-century mathematized natural philosophy. I am not interested in “applying” Fisch’s philosophical theory to a test case in order to verify that “all the pieces fall into place” as much as in exploring the heuristic advantage that, as a historian, I can gain by adopting his philosophical viewpoint. As a historian, I consider myself a humble practitioner. One of the great masters in the history of science, Paolo Rossi, compared the historian to a “straw chair maker” (un impagliatore di sedie) who learns his craft by apprenticeship in a workshop, rather than by applying the rules learned from a textbook. [5] The relationships between history and philosophy is a vexed issue in historical interpretation: somewhat naively perhaps, I believe that philosophy is valuable when it provides me with a toolbox to develop innovative, hopefully even surprising, narratives of past events. Like all craftsmen, I am opportunistic: I use philosophy with a purpose in mind and I can be sometimes incoherent in my adoption of philosophical tools drawn from the works of scholars belonging to different schools. Adherence to factual evidence is of course a rigid constraint for all historians but – to state a truism – facts can be viewed differently. What I appreciate the most about Fisch’s philosophical work is that it is inspirational for my hands-on fieldwork: it allows me to view the past with different eyes, with greater attention to failure, indecision, and ambiguity; a historiographic perspective that is often foreign to the main narrative tools we employ as historians of mathematics, which is to say as people who usually concentrate instead on things like success, achievement, and coherence. Fisch’s view provides historians and philosophers of science with a genuine argument for recovering the contributions of individuals silenced by the historiography of “achievements”: the many historiographical accounts of the incremental progress achieved by “great men.” The episode I will consider is a well-known correspondence between Hooke and Newton that took place in 1679–80. Hooke proposed to Newton a new hypothesis concerning planetary motions. This hypothesis consists of the idea that planets move in the void accelerated by gravitational interactions. Until then, Newton had thought that planets moved because of some sort of interaction with the ether filling the planetary system, as he learnt in his youth by reading Descartes’ Opera. Newton’s ether theory of planetary motion has never been a Cartesian theory based on impact though: the ether that Newton contemplated in his lifetime is composed of particles that repel one another at a distance. One might say that Newton’s is an ether seen from the viewpoint of a natural philosopher who attributes to matter some sort of activity that would have never been endorsed by Descartes. After a failed attempt, which was corrected by Hooke, Newton was able to mathematize the motion of planets gravitationally attracted by the Sun. Hooke offered Newton a valuable suggestion; however, Hooke’s contribution to gravitation theory was minimized by Newton and his acolytes and, as a matter of fact, underappreciated in a way, it remained “invisible,” until recent historiography.
It is appropriate at this juncture to highlight the features of Fisch’s philosophy that I shall attempt to handle as historical tools when framing a narrative of the above episode. (i) A first element is the creative role of Hooke’s ambivalated framework of the planetary system. In the Micrographia (1665), Hooke referred to Descartes as the founding father of the new philosophy pursued at the Royal Society. Indeed, “Descartes is the author to whom Hooke most frequently refers in Micrographia, and the Principia philosophiae is the work he cites most often.” [6] Yet in his correspondence with Newton, Hooke explored a model of planetary interaction based on action at a distance, a model belonging to an anti-mechanistic framework that was well alive in England at the time, and which was shared by those who detected in nature the presence of occult “powers” operating at a distance. The strength of Hooke’s vision very much depends on the unresolved co-presence of two scientific frameworks, one based on the “rules of mechanical motion,” and indebted to Descartes, the other based on the operation of “occult” powers. (ii) Second, I am interested in Fisch’s notion of mediating interlanguages enabling individuals who visit the trading zone to communicate and influence one another. The trading zone, in our case, is the Royal Society and the interaction occurs in the brief yet momentous correspondence between Newton and Hooke taking place in 1679–80. The two correspondents differed in terms of philosophical outlook and mathematical competence (and had already clashed in 1672–6, partly because of these differences). However, they shared a common mathematical language, that of “organic geometry,” which allowed them to talk competently and meaningfully about the new “hypothesis” entertained by Hooke. (iii) Third, the result of this dialogue led Newton to make the transition from a conception of planetary motions as caused by some sort of interaction with the ether to gravitation theory. Newton “changed his mind” rationally after trading ideas with Hooke, ideas framed in terms of a shared mathematical language. (iv) Fourth, Fisch’s model of the trading zone is based on the assumption that this is a space in which individuals meet. Fisch’s Popperian background distances him, in this respect, from the positions shared by Science and Technology Studies (STS) scholars who develop their study of scientific change and scientific controversies at the level of social, rather than individual, actors. Contrariwise, Fisch reformulates an idea that was central to Popper: the idea that scientific creativity is the work of individuals framing bold hypotheses. (v) Fifth, I will give prominence of place to the notion of “invisibility.” Of course, this notion is central not only in Fisch’s work but also in the philosophy of another major protagonist in the history and philosophy of science, Steven Shapin. Shapin, however, sees “the making of scientific knowledge as a fundamentally social activity” and studies those social forces that exclude “technicians,” as a social group, from the historical record, shying away from describing this process of exclusion in individualistic terms, as Fisch does. [7] (vi) This leads me to my sixth and last point. I shall cursorily attempt to indicate the reasons behind Hooke’s centuries-old invisibility in the official historiography of science and the reasons why we have recently changed our historical narratives, so much so that nowadays Hooke’s contribution is considered essential for the development of planetary theory. I will claim that the scientific culture of the early third millennium is propitious for a rehabilitation of Hooke’s role, and in general for a rehabilitation of the role of technicians, as Shapin has made clear in his seminal paper. In doing so, I will position myself outside Fisch’s perspective, which consists in a philosophical analysis that is strictly confined to an internal account of rational scientific change. Here the practitioner of the craft of history will claim some freedom from the need to follow a philosophical theory too consistently: perhaps the humble “impagliatore” has, very marginally, something to offer the theoretician!
2 Hooke’s theory of gravitation
Robert Hooke’s contribution to the theory of gravitation is an interesting case study for probing the fruitfulness of Fisch’s ideas as briefly outlined in Section 1. Indeed, the nature of Hooke’s contributions to mathematized gravitation theory was contested during his own lifetime and gave rise to problematic evaluations until the last century. Hooke has been often contrasted to Newton and Christiaan Huygens as a practitioner and unfavorably compared to a theorist or as a “mechanic of genius rather than a scientist.” [8] Yet from the point of view of his contemporaries, Hooke, because of his dexterity in trading and moving between the diverse locales of London – between watchmakers’ shops, the chambers of the Royal Society, and the laboratory in Gresham College – was better suited to the enterprise of mathematized natural philosophy as envisaged by the Royal Society than the lonely Newton. [9]
Hooke’s social status was lower than that of the other members of the Royal Society. The orphaned son of a Royalist minister, he made his way up the social ladder by entering Westminster School and then gaining a position as chorister at Christ Church in Oxford. Here his meeting with Robert Boyle – an aristocrat who saw religious apologetics and pious natural philosophy as his mission – made his fortune, so much so that Hooke became an influential and respected gentleman of broad learning, who was accepted in the solons of noblemen and who could dine with Archbishops. The Oxford group, gathered around Boyle and John Wilkins, needed Hooke’s experience as a mechanician and his privileged access to the world of painting, mechanical drawing, glassworking, and clockmaking. He was a man who could converse with natural philosophers such as Christopher Wren, Isaac Newton, and Boyle but who could also competently interact with and instruct the practitioners active in London’s workshops.
In 1662, the newly founded Royal Society enrolled Hooke as a paid curator of experiments, an important, pivotal position. True enough, he did remain somewhat of a servant to the other fellows who could request him to perform experiments; and all too often, much at his frustration, he was forced to fight to uphold the uniqueness of his role. Hooke’s lower social status did not allow him to identify with “gentlemen free and unconfin’d” like, say, Boyle. [10] Nonetheless, he wished to distinguish his purposes from the utilitarian aims of the craftsmen with whom he conversed so successfully. He powerfully served the function of relating the world of natural philosophy, dominated by philosophical and theological agendas, to the technological enterprises of mechanical practitioners. Indeed, as Jim Bennett and Ofer Gal have shown, Hooke conceived mechanical tools as instruments of knowledge; objects with which he could think about the microscopic mechanisms (such as the “spring of the air”) underlying macroscopic phenomena accessible to our senses. [11]
In 1679–1680, Hooke addressed Newton letters in which he advanced a new hypothesis concerning the planetary system. Hooke proposed to view the planetary system as constituted by mutually gravitating bodies. The hypothesis in question was not new: it had already partly been presented by Hooke in some lectures to the Royal Society as early as May 1666 and had later been published – in 1674 – in an essay entitled An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth by Observations dedicated to his astronomical observations aimed to determine stellar parallax. Hooke brought to the attention of his readers a “System of the World” that differed “in many particulars from any yet known” and that was in compliance with the “common Rules of Mechanical Motions.” [12] Hooke’s 1674 essay was reviewed in the Philosophical Transactions, and his planetary theory was thus given wide circulation. [13]
The new Hookean system depended on three “suppositions.” In these suppositions, Hooke merged two opposing scientific frameworks: the “mechanical philosophy,” most notably as expounded by Descartes, and the “magnetic philosophy,” proposed in England by John Dee, Francis Bacon, William Gilbert, Christopher Wren, among others. [14] The first supposition was that all celestial bodies have an “attraction or gravitating power towards their own Centers. Whereby they attract not only their own parts […] but that they do also attract all other Celestial Bodies that are within the sphere of their activity.” It seems that Hooke conceived of this “sphere of activity” as finite and that in 1678 he perhaps changed his mind on the universality of the attracting gravitational force: for in that year he gave to the press one of his Cutlerian lectures in which it was argued that comets are acted upon by the Sun’s “gravitating power” in a different way (one that in certain conditions might cause “protrusion” rather than attraction) compared to the planets. [15] The second supposition, drawn from Descartes, was that all bodies move in straight uniform motion until they are “deflected and bent” by some “effectual powers” in “a Circle, an Ellipsis [sic], or some other more compounded Curve Line.” The third supposition was that the “attractive powers” are “so much the more powerful in operating, by how much the nearer” the bodies are to the centers of attraction. Hooke described the way in which the planets of the solar system are attracted by the gravitational power of the sun and how they attract each other influencing “considerably” their motions and hoped that astronomers could determine the law of variation of the gravitational powers in order to reduce “all the Coelestial Motions to a certain rule.” [16]
The correspondence between Hooke and Newton carried out in the Winter 1679–80 shows that these three suppositions caught the Lucasian Professor totally unprepared. Until then Newton had envisaged the motion of the planets as caused by a ether filling the planetary system, as it is apparent in his “An Hypothesis Explaining the Properties of Light,” which he had sent Henry Oldenburg in December 1675. Newton had then reiterated the concept in a famous letter to Robert Boyle in February 1679, in which he proposed a different ether model compared to that of the “Hypothesis.” [17] In both cases Newton envisaged the ether in ways that cannot be defined in Cartesian mechanistic terms: the particles composing the Newtonian ether are indeed endowed with some sort of activity, while for Descartes matter is passive. However, Newton shared with Descartes the idea that the interplanetary space is filled with matter. According to Hooke, instead, the motions of the planets occur in empty space, and the mechanician can predict their orbital motions by “compounding the celestiall motions of the planetts of a direct motion by the tangent & an attractive motion towards the centrall body [of the Sun].” [18] Further, Hooke assumed that the attraction of the Sun decreases with the inverse square of the distance; and in January 1680, he asked Newton to provide a demonstration of what would be the curve traced by a planet subject to a force of this kind. [19]
Hooke was very tentatively proposing to Newton a hypothesis on the causes of planetary motions indebted to the explanation in terms of action-at-a-distance magnetism that had been considered by several natural philosophers, from William Gilbert and Johannes Kepler to Christopher Wren. [20] In the “magnetic philosophy,” however, planets move because of a magnetic, rather than a gravitational interaction. Hooke’s planetary model was based on the hypothesis that what causes planetary motion is action-at-a-distance gravitation, an occult force banned by the mechanical philosophy as envisaged by Descartes and Thomas Hobbes. However, Hooke described his system as based on the “common rules” of mechanics. One might be tempted to characterize his model as “ambivalent,” or at least, sufficiently complex to address the desiderata of a broad range of natural philosophers.
For sure, Hooke was uncertain about his hypothesis, and that is why he asked Newton’s expert opinion. His letters to Newton have a very tentative character. In the first place, Hooke was unable to provide a mathematical proof of gravitation theory, as he candidly made clear, asking Newton for one. Further, he suggested several experiments with pendulums aimed at verifying his hypothesis. He hoped to measure a variation in the period of oscillation at different heights (e.g., at foot and at the top of St. Paul’s Cathedral). [21] We are confronted here with a momentous framework shift promoted by an actor – Hooke – who was very appreciative of the mechanical philosophy (as it is apparent from his Preface to the Micrographia (1665)) but who was also interested in considering action-at-a-distance characteristic of the alternative magnetic philosophy. Hooke’s position was indeed a hybrid between the two competing philosophies, the mechanical and the magnetic.
Until 1679, Newton had embraced planetary models whereby planets move around the Sun because of the action of a medium filling the interplanetary spaces. [22] The shift to the new model based on void and gravitation is unanimously considered in the literature as a decisive revolution in Newton’s intellectual development. But how could Newton, to make use of the title of this special issue, “change his mind”? I have no space to enter into the details concerning the making of the Principia from 1679 to 1687 and I will not even attempt to broach the complex historiographical issues concerning the nature of Newton’s ether hypotheses: what I would like to underline here is that this is a change that implied new norms of what can be considered as a valid explanation of natural phenomena. In the framework dominating Newton’s mind before the correspondence with Hooke, a medium filling the interplanetary spaces was causally responsible of planetary motions. In the new Hookean framework, instead, a gravitational interaction acting in void was accepted as a causal explanation, insofar as it could be mathematically deduced from the planetary phenomena. Newton was soon to discover that Hooke’s model could be mathematized in a very successful way. One might contend that it is mostly because of such mathematical fruitfulness that Newton was eventually led to embrace Hooke’s hypothesis, which, of course, is at the basis of the Principia.
It is the correspondence with Hooke that tore a veil from Newton's eyes, allowing him to see very far. From the available documentary evidence it is not clear, however, how far Newton could see in 1680. According to some scholars, it was at this time that he first developed an outline of the theory of gravitation. It is considered likely that in early 1680 Newton managed to prove that the first two laws of Kepler imply that the planets are attracted to the Sun by a force that varies with the inverse square of the distance. According to others, things are not so straightforward. [23] It is often said that, although the credit goes to Hooke for having turned Newton away from his ether model, he cannot claim the merit of having provided a mathematical formulation of the new model. It is one thing – we are often told – to advance a qualitative hypothesis (the planets move in a vacuum in which they are deflected from inertial straight trajectories by a gravitational force directed toward the Sun), and quite another to provide a mathematical demonstration. The weakness of Hooke’s mathematics would also be evident – according to some scholars – from the fact that, as appears from his correspondence with Newton, he believed that the speed of a planet is inversely proportional to its distance from the Sun, a law that is not compatible with Kepler's law of areas. [24] Thus, in the end, we should agree with Hall for whom – as we know – Hooke might at most be called a “mechanic of genius” rather than a “scientist.” [25]
Recent documentary discoveries and a different sensitivity toward the complex meanings of the terms “mathematics” and “scientist,” when such terms are evaluated in their historical context, have led to a dismissal of Hall's drastic judgment. Patri Pugliese discovered that Hooke resorted to graphic constructions of trajectories (see Figure 1) which allowed him to mathematize central force motion. Nauenberg has detailed Hooke’s use of experiences with pendulums and balls rolled onto concave surfaces in order to verify the shape of the trajectories traced by bodies accelerated by central forces. [26] These geometric constructions and experiences operate as a kind of graphical and mechanical simulation of planetary motions and should be viewed by the historian as methods belonging to the mathematical sciences, in the broad sense that the term “mathematics” had in the seventeenth century. An important feature of the mechanical philosophy was the use of artificial instruments such as pendulums, springs, and inclined planes as a means to shed light on the causes of natural phenomena, since the latter were thought to be generated by mechanical causes. [27] Hooke investigated the mathematical structure of the planetary system using graphical models and mechanical devices, tools that were familiar in the practice of the mechanicians active in London in his times. Rather than criticizing Hooke on the basis of anachronistic normative values about what “good” mathematics should be, it is more appropriate for the historian to accept that his mechanical practice was considered the right way to proceed within the community of inventors and virtuosi who were pursuing natural philosophy by resorting to the “mixed mathematical sciences.” [28]

In September 1685, apparently after seeing Newton’s “De motu corporum in gyrum” (the embryonic manuscript that gave rise to the Principia), Hooke wrote a manuscript on central force motion that graphically implements his 1674 hypothesis on planetary motions. Here Hooke constructs a polygonal approximation to the elliptical trajectory traced by a body attracted by a central force whose intensity is proportional to distance (Hooke’s law). His technique, probably derived from the first theorem of Newton’s “De motu” (MS Add. 3965.7, fols 55r-62bisr, Cambridge Univesrity Library), consists in compounding tangential inertial motion with displacements directed towards the center and whose length is proportional to the force’s intensity. The impulsive force (the “puls of gravity”) is assumed to act at instants separated by equal intervals of time. This manuscript is discussed in Pugliese, “Robert Hooke and the Dynamics of Motion” and Nauenberg, “Robert Hooke’s Seminal Contribution.” Source: Trinity College, Cambridge. MS O.lla.116. By courtesy of the Master and Fellows of Trinity College (Cambridge).
The case of Hooke’s theory of gravitation, its invisibility for official historiography and its impact on Newton that we have briefly considered above raises interesting questions that can be broached within the framework of Fisch’s theses on “trading zones” and the creative role of “ambivalence,” since Hooke was literally trading between natural philosophers accustomed to handle astronomical data and mathematical formulas and practitioners skilled in drawing diagrams and manipulating machines. In doing so, he fostered a mediated dialogue and cooperation between individuals who belonged to socially separated groups and who adopted ways of life and languages that rarely mixed one with the other. Hooke thereby promoted the professional training he had received in the smoky workshops of London as something that amounted to much more than just manual dexterity. His familiarity with mechanical tools was an instrument for discovery that, as we have seen, was inspirational for Newton. The “mechanic of genius” had a great deal to teach to the true scientist and natural philosopher.
One might claim, at this juncture, that the category of “ambivalated” individual can be applied to Hooke. In the Preface to the Micrographia (1665), Hooke had defended Cartesian mechanism as a grounding feature of the new philosophy pursued at the Royal Society. Hooke shared the Cartesian view according to which matter is ultimately composed of corpuscles and that the microscopic “texture of matter” and the interactions of corpuscles could explain all phenomena. The inner workings of nature, he claimed, could be accounted for in terms of interactions between “compounding particles of matter” that might eventually be even observed through the help of some improved microscope. [29] Hooke’s planetary hypothesis, though, was based both on the Cartesian “rules of mechanics” and on the idea that powers acting at a distance are the cause of planetary motions. A second model, familiar to the followers of “occult” forces, such as John Dee, William Gilbert, and Francis Bacon, was superimposed upon the mechanical one in a way that is characteristic of quite a number of English seventeenth-century natural philosophers. [30] One might claim, with John Henry, that this merging of occult philosophy with the mechanical one is what paved the way to Newton’s gravitation theory. [31] Without this ambivalated co-presence of two competing, apparently conflicting frameworks, we would not have had the creative shift, the “change of mind,” that lay the groundwork for the Principia.
Yet, I would like to stress another point here concerning the language that allowed Newton and Hooke to exchange views on planetary motion. The mathematical language they employed was that familiar at the time to those mathematical practitioners intent on studying the mechanical generation of curves via the handling of instruments made of sliding rulers and strings. The mathematical practitioners active in the early modern period often saw a curve-tracing device not so much as a theoretical construct but as an instrument to be applied in one’s workshop. The curve traced by an instrument could serve as the conic surface of a lens, the hyperboloid surface of the fusee of a clock, the cycloidal shape of the teeth of a wheel, or the stereographic projection of the lines of equal azimuth of the celestial sphere. Knowledge of the construction and handling of mechanical instruments was part of the mathematical repertoire not only of Hooke, the mechanical practitioner, but also of Newton, the mathematician. And one might contend that it is such an overlapping between the mathematical practices of Hooke and Newton that allowed them to enter into a fruitful dialogue: they were deploying – so to speak – a mathematical “interlanguage.” The two met in a trading zone in which they (litigiously) dialogued by using a mathematical pidgin language that was part of the mathematical toolboxes of both the Lucasian Professor, mathematically trained by reading Descartes’, Barrow’s and Wallis’s works, and the Royal Society Secretary, instructed in the mechanical practices of the London mathematical practitioners.
The interest in the use of mechanical instruments in geometrical constructions was so alive that a discipline called geometria organica (from the Greek word organon for instrument) was atop the agenda not only of mechanical practitioners, as Hooke, but also of many highbrow mathematicians, including Descartes. The latter filled his Géométrie (1637/1954) with curve-tracing devices (composite compasses, rulers equipped with strings and pulleys) that he deployed in the Dioptrique as parts of lens-grinding machines he discussed with skilled opticians such as Jean Ferrier. [32] The geometria organica was cultivated also by one of the most prolific Dutch mathematicians, Frans van Schooten, who right from the title page of his treatise (1646) made it clear that he was not simply interested in pure geometry: for his work, he emphasized, was useful not only to geometers but also to opticians, designers of sundials, and mechanicians (the title runs: De Organica Conicarum Sectionum in Plano Descriptione Tractatus: Geometris, Opticis, Praesertim Vero Gnomonicis & Mechanicis Utilis). Christiaan Huygens with his Horologium Oscillatorium (1673) offered another influential example of interaction between the study of mechanical curves (such as the cycloid) and geometrical constructions applied to natural philosophy as well as to mechanics (horology). Organic geometry was the interlanguage deployed by Hooke and Newton in the trading zone of the Royal Society.
As a mathematician, Newton was very much interested in organic geometry, in the tracing of curves via mechanical instruments. Most notably – as he informed John Collins, a prominent mathematical practitioner active in London, in 1672 – he devised a new method for the tracing of conics and higher order curves. [33] Therefore, he shared with Hooke mathematical competences and interests that allowed the two natural philosophers to exchange ideas and “communicate across a cultural border,” [34] that separating the practitioner from the university professor. Organic geometry was their inter-language, to use Fisch’s terminology, and the Royal Society was the, conflictual (!), zone where they traded their views on light (in 1672–1676) and planetary motions (from 1679). But Newton was a mathematician who had other languages and concepts in his toolbox that were foreign to Hooke’s background knowledge. Newton was the discoverer of a method to calculate the radius of curvature of a plane curve, a technique that allowed him to graphically approximate planetary trajectories according to Hooke’s hypothesis in a powerful way. It is this technique that, as Nauenberg has demonstrated, allowed Newton to formulate Hooke’s hypothesis in a more satisfactory way. [35] Instead of graphing the trajectory by means of the composition of motions via the parallelogram rule (as Hooke did, see Figure 1), Newton drew the trajectory by calculating the radius of curvature (given his knowledge of the law “the radius of curvature is proportional to speed squared, divided by the normal component of central force”) and approximating it piecewise as a series of circular trajectories. This technique afforded Newton a better approximation. If we follow closely the correspondence between Hooke and Newton, we discover that at first Newton made a mistake, which Hooke corrected: he calculated that a body attracted by a constant gravitational force toward the center of the Earth (“a body B let fall and it’s gravity will give it a new motion towards the centre of ye Earth”) would spiral down toward the center (“describing in its fall a spiral line”). [36] Hooke replied that, rather, the body would move between a pericenter and an apocenter describing a curve akin to an ellipse (“my theory of circular motion makes me suppose it [the curve] would be very differing and nothing att all akin to a spirall but rather a kind of Elliptueid”). [37] After a few days, Newton was able to solve this rather thorny problem, setting the record straight: he showed that the trajectory will be neither a spiral nor an oval (e.g., an ellipse) but rather a precessing orbit with a large apsidal advance. [38]
It is a reasonable guess that Newton “changed his mind” – a phenomenon of rational framework transition on which Fisch strongly insists – when he realized that his mathematics allowed him to mathematicize Hooke’s hypothesis: this is what made the hypothesis so interesting for Newton. To mathematicise an ether theory of planetary motion is a Herculean task, one that not even Leonhard Euler was able to fulfill, almost a century later. Indeed, vortex fluid motion could be mathematically tackled only in the nineteenth century in terms of the Navier–Stokes equations. Physical models can be tackled by mathematical tools that are not always available when they are first conceived. Quantum fields are a wonderful model for studying the interaction of matter with radiation, but, until the techniques of renormalization were developed, the calculated amplitudes in quantum electrodynamics were all meaningless infinities (I am thinking of the notorious divergences that plagued theoretical physics in the mid-twentieth century). It is reasonable to surmise that the force that led Newton to move beyond the ether model and to accept an action-at-a-distance model was the realization that Hooke’s hypothesis was approachable by mathematical tools at his disposal. Notice that I am not reiterating here the thesis according to which Hooke was a poor mathematician compared to Newton. This might be true, but it is not the issue at stake here. The difference between the two correspondents affording Newton an advantage over Hooke was slighter than one might think. Newton’s advantage boiled down to a detail: a technique to calculate the radius of curvature of a plane curve – a technique, for sure, that Newton had mastered since his discovery of the fluxional method. One should not too hastily conclude that Hooke was incompetent in mathematics and that Newton’s superiority as a mathematician explains his success in the 1679–1680 correspondence. [39] As a matter of fact, Newton was deploying a very simple graphic technique. Newton was not integrating a differential equation, of the sort we might find in a textbook of “Newtonian” mechanics nowadays; rather, very much like Hooke, he used pen, straightedge and compass, in order to carefully draw an approximating curve on paper.
It might be contended that it is exactly the mechanical character of Hooke’s mathematical methods (his geometria organica) that led many historians in the past to disqualify Hooke’s intellectual endeavor as not pertaining to “true science.” [40] These historians have projected the modernity of “Newtonian” mechanics onto Newton, failing to realize that the two correspondents were speaking the same mathematical language. This might be an example of the phenomenon of the “invisibility in official historiography” of trading zone mediators that has been underlined by Fisch. As we have seen above, Hooke was quite invisible in the works by I. Bernard Cohen and Rupert Hall, two mid-twentieth century masters in the history of science who, influenced as they were by Alexandre Koyré’s interpretation of the “scientific revolution” as the outcome of the mathematical visions of a few great giants (Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, Descartes and Newton), were prevented from attributing great importance to the Royal Society’s Curator of Experiments. [41] When Koyré, Cohen, and Hall were writing their influential historical narratives, the popular models of what it is to be a scientist were the likes of Einstein and Heisenberg: theoretical physicists who, basing their mathematical constructions on philosophical principles and abstractions, could deliver predictions that received spectacular confirmation. It is only recently that Hooke’s reputation has been “restored,” as Lisa Jardine puts it in. [42]
Lately, there has been a proliferation of studies on Hooke and, at this juncture, it is fitting to ask why Hooke’s fortune has changed recently, so much so that a commemorative plaque to him has been unveiled in Westminster Abbey, just in front of the funerary monument of his great enemy, Sir Isaac Newton. [43] There is no easy answer to this question, and in searching for one I will complement Fisch’s internal account of rational change with a historiographical perspective based on the idea that the context in which the historian lives determines his narrative: we always view the past – to state a truism – through the conceptual frameworks provided by our present standpoint. The fact that Hooke is given pride of place in recent accounts of seventeenth-century natural philosophy is consequence of a re-evaluation of the role played by engineers and mechanicians in the development of early-modern science, and of a shift of interest from mathematics and astronomy (the two disciplines that informed the Koyrean and Sartonian narratives of the scientific revolution) to mixed mathematics, hydrology, pneumatics, biology, medicine, microscopy, geology, and alchemy. [44] But perhaps, even more deeply, our perspective has changed because of the recent advent of new scientific paradigms dominated by computer simulations and performative technologies. Hooke, the practitioner who tested his new theory of planetary motion by letting spheres roll on conical surfaces or observing pendular motion, the “organic” geometer who graphically reconstructed central force motion might be viewed as a precursor of computer modeling. His social status and scientific practice somewhat resemble those of practitioners of nanotechnology and genetic engineering, who often find themselves active in “extra-mural science,” scientific enterprises located outside academia driven by a know-how that is nurtured in the manipulations performed in the laboratory and shared with technicians and entrepreneurs, rather than in theoretical conversations with postdocs and grown-up colleagues in the department seminar. Such analogies are of course perilous: they can lead to Whiggism as much as the parallel of Newton with Einstein once did. Yet such analogies act, mostly tacitly, in orienting today the historians’ perspective along angles that allow the emergence from oblivion of Hooke as an important, ambivalent, mediator between the “dark shops” of glass- and clockmakers and the rooms of aristocrats and high-ranking clergymen who turned to natural philosophy for the pursuit of religious apologetics. Hooke’s ambiguous position between these two groups, one might further contend, was in part responsible for his invisibility. He occupied too low a position to figure as a conspicuous collaborator of his patrons, Christopher Wren and Robert Boyle. Hooke was aware of the important role as a mediator between the “cultures of skill and those of learning” that he was playing. [45] In the dedication to Sir John Cutler in the Micrographia he wrote:
This Gentlemen [Cutler] has well observ’d, that the Arts of Life have been too long imprison’d in the dark shops of Mechanicks themselves, & there hindred from growth, either by ignorance, or self-interest; and he has bravely freed them from these inconveniences. [46]
3 Hooke’s and Newton’s contrasting views on mathematical method
As we have seen in Section 2, what is at stake in evaluating Hooke’s contribution to gravitation theory is a conflict about what can be counted as good or “true” mathematics. It is in part this conflict that generated the anxieties that inflamed the clash between Hooke and Newton, and it is this conflict that generated diverging readings of the relative importance of the two English natural philosophers. In this section, I will suggest that Hooke and Newton clashed not only because of a conflict generated by priority claims. They diverged on rather deeply felt issues concerning the nature and role of mathematics in natural philosophy. One might say that the Royal Society was the conflictual “trading zone” where Hooke and Newton confronted opposing norms concerning how natural philosophy should be practiced. Unfortunately, it is often the case that the confrontation between Hooke and Newton is reduced to simply an issue of priority. This is a reading that the two protagonists of the dispute themselves helped to shape.
Indeed, when Hooke learnt about the imminent publication of the Principia, he was vocal in claiming his priority: he could find very little appreciation of his contributions in Newton’s opus magnum. To those who sided with Hooke, it was plain that the Royal Society’s Secretary had been robbed of a decisive contribution in the understanding of the planetary system. Hooke’s friend, the diarist John Aubrey, on September 15, 1689, pleaded for Hooke’s case by writing in despair to the antiquarian Anthony à Wood, who was then composing his Athenae Oxonienses:
Mr Wood! This [gravitation] is the greatest discovery in nature that ever was since the world’s creation: it never was so much as hinted by any man before. I know you will doe him [Hooke] right. [47]
Yet Hooke’s contribution to gravitation theory was forgotten in the eighteenth century, a period in which the status of practitioners of analytical mechanics, who conceived themselves as the heirs of the Newtonian program expounded in the Principia, raised high in the scientific academies.
For the mathematicians of the Enlightenment, Newton’s disparaging evaluation of Hooke’s contribution to gravitation theory was non-problematically true:
Now is not this very fine? Mathematicians [like Newton himself] that find out, settle & do all the business must content themselves with being nothing but dry calculators & drudges & another [Hooke] that does nothing but pretend & grasp at all things must carry away all the invention. [48]
Newton was writing the above lines in 1686 to Edmond Halley who had informed him about Hooke’s claims in the discovery of universal gravitation. These claims, as we know, were not accepted. But Newton’s victory was far from being as straightforward as one might think by projecting on historical actors conceptions about the role and nature of mathematized science that were only accepted as uncontroversial much later. If we look somewhat more closely at Newton’s interactions with the Royal Society, we discover that his conceptions of mathematized natural philosophy were initially rejected. Further, Newton himself was at pains to integrate the new mathematics he had so successfully developed in his youth within the philosophical agenda that he had been endorsing from the mid-1670s onward. Anxiety and ambivalence were not foreign to the greatest hero of the scientific revolution.
Newton had become a member of the Royal Society in 1672 after having presented his reflection telescope to the society. This innovation fitted well with the desiderata of the newly established institution, which assigned great importance to microscopy and the improvement of telescopic observations. As is well-known, in 1672 Newton submitted his famous paper on the experimentum crucis, in which he claimed to have proved a new theory concerning light and colors. The theory had already received a thorough treatment in the Lucasian lectures on optics that Newton had deposited in 1672 and dated retrospectively from 1670. In the third lecture, he stated that by the use of “geometry” the science of colors, and natural philosophy in general, could achieve the “greatest evidence.” He also expressed his annoyance toward those natural philosophers who were confining themselves to “conjectures and probabilities.” [49] Newton might have had Hooke in mind here, since in his Micrographia (1665) the latter had warned readers to consider any “small Conjectures” concerning the “causes of things” contained in the book as simply “doubtful Problems, and uncertain ghesses.” [50] Hooke was expressing values deeply felt in the Royal Society.
One should bear in mind that, just after the Restoration, many natural philosophers belonging to the Royal Society wished to make it clear that no “unquestionable” or “dogmatic conclusions” should be feared from them. Politically opinionated philosophers, or dogmatic theologians, were not admitted into the society, which instead promoted a mitigated skepticism that could protect its fellows from the politically risky positions epitomized by Hobbes’s or Spinoza’s metaphysics. [51] As one could read in the influential manifesto by Thomas Sprat, The History of the Royal Society, experimental philosophy “never separates us into mortal Factions”: it is by avoiding the “enthusiasm and dogmatism” dominant during the Interregnum that the Royal Society’s fellows were free to “raise contrary imaginations […] without danger of Civil War.” [52] That is why any discourse aimed at reaching certainty was looked upon with suspicion, while skepticism and probabilism were approved of in some of the most influential Royal Society manifestos, such as Hooke’s masterpiece on microscopy, Sprat’s History, and Joseph Glanvill’s Scepsis Scientifica (1665).
In his Lucasian lectures on optics and his 1672 paper, Newton broke with this code of behavior by stating that the theory of colors he was proposing – a topic that he knew was regarded as “belonging to physics” – was not “an hypothesis but most rigid consequence.” [53] The fact that Newton’s mathematized optical theory of colors was presented in ways not acceptable to the Royal Society is made manifest by the fact that the above statement was censored by Henry Oldenburg, the secretary of the Royal Society. To most fellows of the Royal Society, Hooke’s mechanical mathematics was a much more congenial enterprise.
Hooke was always careful to present his mathematized natural philosophy as conjectural and hypothetical (he made it clear that his gravitation theory was a hypothesis based on suppositions). Moreover, his mechanical and graphical mathematics, contrary to Newton’s, could be understood by all the fellows, as it did not require mathematical training and could be made persuasive through well-orchestrated public displays, rather than a solitary exercise of reason. All these features of Hookean organic mathematics resonated with values, such as experimentalism and the public accessibility of demonstrations, promoted at the Royal Society.
When Newton produced his bulky Principia, very few could read his demonstrations and grasp the usefulness of the abstract mathematized planetary theory (Guicciardini (1999)). Halley had to make a serious effort to have the book accepted at the Royal Society by insisting on its alleged usefulness for the arts of gunnery and navigation. [54] One should not conclude, however, that Newton, his robust methodology notwithstanding, viewed the new mathematized sciences of colors and gravitation that he had immensely helped to shape without anxiety. On the contrary, an analysis of his manuscripts, correspondence, and publication policies reveals how difficult it was for him to integrate the new algebraic methods of series and fluxions within the complex web of beliefs that he had come to endorse in the mid-1670s. He began framing his ruminations on mathematical method in terms of a sharp opposition between the methods of the moderns (epitomized by Descartes) and those of the ancients, as revealed by Pappus’s Collectiones (1588), which he avidly read. Newton began searching for the hidden method of discovery of the ancients, the Analysis Veterum, more beautiful and concise, and more powerful (he claimed), compared to the Cartesian approach to geometry in terms of symbols. The Cartesian algebraic geometry in which he had so wonderfully excelled in his youth now gave him “nausea.” [55] Algebra he conceded – according to a memorandum by David Gregory – is “fit enough to find out, but entirely unfit to consign to writing and commit to posterity.” [56] These methodological convictions of Newton the mathematician resonated in complex ways with his views on the wisdom of the ancients and his philosophically pronounced anti-Cartesianism. Even though the historian who is interested in these aspects of Newton’s complex intellectual biography risks drawing oversimplified implications between diverse aspects of Newton’s intellectual endeavor (those pertaining to mathematics and those pertaining to history and religion), this historiographical challenge is worth facing, as it allows us to probe his authorial strategies. As time went on, Newton lost no chance to depict himself as an heir of the ancients geometers rather than as a follower of the “mathematicians of recent times,” whom he despised. [57]
The contrast with Hooke is striking. The curator of experiments, and from 1679 secretary of the Royal Society, portrayed himself as a representative of the new burgeoning class of mechanicians and entrepreneurs active in London for the promotion of useful knowledge and profiled himself as a follower of both Baconian experientialism and of moderate Cartesian hypotheticism. He viewed himself as the promoter of a new philosophy which in principle could restore part of the knowledge of the natural world which mankind had lost after the fall from Eden. [58] The Lucasian Professor, instead, aimed at certain knowledge, despised conjectural hypotheticism, and viewed himself as the restorer of a pristine Noachian wisdom corrupted because of idolatry. As a natural philosopher, he rejected those Cartesian mechanical conjectures that, he claimed, were “blazoned about everywhere.” [59] Hooke’s and Newton’s contrasting views on mathematical method and the role of mathematization in natural philosophy are related in complex ways to the conflicting narratives that the two men constructed and divulged. Indeed, part of the passionate polemic between Newton and Hooke was framed in terms of different historical narratives on the development (and corruption) of natural philosophy and mathematics.
As we have seen in this section, Hooke and Newton in many ways endorsed different norms on how mathematics should be deployed in natural philosophy. Yet as we have detailed in Section 2, Hooke was able to “destabilize,” as Fisch would put it, [60] Newton and induce a momentous framework transition in the Lucasian Professor’s mind.
4 Conclusion
The historical case we have considered in Sections 2 and 3 – the influence of Hooke on Newton’s theory of gravitation – is emblematic of the anxious confrontations on mathematical method and natural philosophy that characterize the long seventeenth century. If we allow ourselves to make full use of Fisch’s jargon, we can conclude by saying that Hooke, an “invisible” individual for official historiography, forged a hypothetical explanation of planetary motions in terms of action-at-a-distance gravitation, and he did so “from within” a Baconian agenda that “ambivalatingly” merged features of the mechanical and the occult philosophies. Hooke was successful in this proposal because of his ability to talk and trade between different groups, the natural philosophers of the Royal Society and the practitioners of the arsenal and shops of London. The open questions on planetary motions of the natural philosophers found an answer in the mechanical and graphical instruments of the practitioners. Hooke’s new “Hypothesis” on the “System of the World” was the gift he handed Newton, who transformed it and brought it to a level of mathematical sophistication that will be received since the eighteenth century as the crowning moment of the “Scientific Revolution.” There is no doubt that it was Newton who achieved the mathematization of the theory of gravitation. Yet, as Fisch has thought us, we should not only focus on achievements but appreciate also the creative role of individuals who, by visiting a trading zone equipped with a “mathematical pidgin,” a language fit for the trade of ideas, have fostered a rational framework change.
Acknowledgements
This research was funded by the Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” of the University of Milan under the Project “Departments of Excellence 2018–2022” awarded by the Ministry of Education, University and Research (MIUR). I thank two anonymous referees for precious advice.
References
Aubrey, John. Brief Lives: Chiefly of Contemporaries: Set down by John Aubrey between the years 1669 & 1696, edited by Andrew Clark. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1898.Search in Google Scholar
Barrow, Isaac. Lectiones Opticae et Geometricae. London: Godbid, 1674.Search in Google Scholar
Bennett, Jim A. “Hooke and Wren and the System of the World: Some Points Towards An Historical Account.” The British Journal for the History of Science 8:1 (1975), 32–61.10.1017/S0007087400013698Search in Google Scholar
Bennett, Jim A. “The Mechanics’ Philosophy and the Mechanical Philosophy.” History of Science 24 (1986), 1–28.10.1177/007327538602400101Search in Google Scholar
Bennett, Jim A., Cooper, Michael, Hunter, Michael, and Lisa, Jardine, eds. London’s Leonardo: The Life and Work of Robert Hooke. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.Search in Google Scholar
Bertoloni Melil, Domenico. Thinking with Objects: The Transformation of Mechanics in the Seventeenth Century. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006.Search in Google Scholar
Bos, Henk J. M. Redefining Geometrical Exactness: Descartes’ Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction. New York: Springer, 2001.10.1007/978-1-4613-0087-8Search in Google Scholar
Brown, Gary I. “The Evolution of the Term ‘Mixed Mathematics.’” Journal of the History of Ideas 52:1 (1991), 81–102.10.2307/2709583Search in Google Scholar
Burnett, D. Graham. Descartes and the Hyperbolic Quest: Lens Making Machines and Their Significance in the Seventeenth Century. Philadelphia, PA: American Philosophical Society, 2005.Search in Google Scholar
Cohen, I. Bernard. The Newtonian Revolution, with Illustrations of the Transformation of Scientific Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.Search in Google Scholar
Cooper, Michael, and Hunter, Michael, eds. Robert Hooke: Tercentennial Studies. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.Search in Google Scholar
Descartes, René. The Geometry of René Descartes with a Facsimile of the First Edition, edited and translated by D. E. Smith, M. L. Latham. New York: Dover, 1637/1954.Search in Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Émilie (Gabrielle-Émilie le Tonnelier de Breteuil, Marquise Du Châtelet-Lomont). “Exposition abregée du système du monde, et explication des principaux Phénomenes astronomiques tirée des Principes de M. Newton.” Appendix to Isaac Newton, Principes mathématiques de la philosophie naturelle par feue madame la marquise Du Chastellet, vol. 2. Paris: Desaint & Saillant, 1759.Search in Google Scholar
Fisch, Menachem. Creatively Undecided: Toward a History and Philosophy of Scientific Agency. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2017.10.7208/chicago/9780226514659.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Fisch, Menachem, and Benbaji, Yitzhak. The View from Within: Normativity and the Limits of Self-Criticism. Notre Dame (IN): University of Notre Dame Press, 2011.Search in Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael. Dynamics of Reason: The 1999 Kant Lectures at Stanford University. Stanford: CSLI Publications, 2001.Search in Google Scholar
Gal, Ofer. “Producing Knowledge in the Workshop: Hooke’s “Inflection” from Optics to Planetary Motion.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27 (1996), 181–205.10.1016/0039-3681(95)00035-6Search in Google Scholar
Gal, Ofer. Meanest Foundations and Nobler Superstructure: Hooke, Newton and “the Compounding of the Celestiall Motions of the Planetts.” Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002.10.1007/978-94-017-2223-0Search in Google Scholar
Galison, Peter L. Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997.Search in Google Scholar
Glanvill, Joseph. Scepsis Scientifica: Or, Confest Ignorance, the Way to Science, in an Essay of the Vanity of Dogmatizing, and Confident Opinion, With a Reply to the Exceptions of the Learned Thomas Albius. London: E. Cotes, for H. Eversden, 1665.Search in Google Scholar
Guicciardini, Niccolò. Reading the Principia: The Debate on Newton’s Mathematical Methods for Natural Philosophy from 1687 to 1736. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.10.1017/CBO9780511524752Search in Google Scholar
Guicciardini, Niccolò, ed. “Open Forum: Newton vs. Hooke on Gravitation.” Early Science and Medicine 10:4 (2005), 510–43.10.1163/157338205774661825Search in Google Scholar
Guicciardini, Niccolò. Isaac Newton on Mathematical Certainty and Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009.10.7551/mitpress/9780262013178.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Hall, A. Rupert. “Robert Hooke and Horology.” Notes and Records of the Royal Society 8:2 (1951), 167–77.10.1098/rsnr.1951.0016Search in Google Scholar
Henry, John. “Occult Qualities and the Experimental Philosophy: Active Principles in Pre-Newtonian Matter Theory.” History of Science 24 (1986), 335–81.10.4324/9781351219303-3Search in Google Scholar
Henry, John. “The Fragmentation of Renaissance Occultism and the Decline of Magic.” History of Science 46 (2008), 1–48.10.4324/9781351219303-10Search in Google Scholar
Hooke, Robert. Micrographia: Or, Some Physiological Descriptions of Minute Bodies Made by Magnifying Glasses, With Observations and Inquiries Thereupon. London: J. Martyn and J. Allestry, 1665.Search in Google Scholar
Hooke, Robert. “Motion in a Curve: A Statement of Planetary Movements as a Mechanical Problem.” In Early Science in Oxford, vol. 6: The Life and Work of Robert Hooke (Part 1), edited by R. T. Gunther, 265-8. Oxford: for the Author, 1666/1930.Search in Google Scholar
Hooke, Robert. An Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth from Observations. London: John Martyn, 1674.Search in Google Scholar
Hooke, Robert. Lectures and Collections, Made by Robert Hooke, Secretary of the Royal Society. Cometa […] Microscopium […]. London: John Martyn, 1678.Search in Google Scholar
Hospital, Guillaume F. A. de, Analyse des infiniment petits pour l'intelligence des lignes courbes. Paris: Imprimerie Royale, 1696.Search in Google Scholar
Hunter, Michael, and Schaffer, Simon, eds. Robert Hooke, New Studies. Woodbridge: The Boydell Press, 1989.Search in Google Scholar
Hunter, Michael. “Hooke the Natural Philosopher.” In London’s Leonardo: The Life and Work of Robert Hooke, edited by Jim Bennett, Michael Cooper, Michael Hunter, Lisa Jardine, 105–62. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.Search in Google Scholar
Huygens, Christiaan. Horologium Oscillatorium: Sive, De Motu Pendulorum ad Horologia Aptato Demonstrationes Geometricae. Paris: F. Muguet, 1673.10.5479/sil.127979.39088002701910Search in Google Scholar
Iliffe, Robert. “Material Doubts: Hooke, Artisan Culture and the Exchange of Information in 1670s London.” British Journal of the History of Science 28 (1995), 285–318.10.1017/S0007087400033173Search in Google Scholar
Inwood, Stephen. The Man Who Knew Too Much: The Strange and Inventive Life of Robert Hooke 1635–1703. London: Macmillan, 2002.Search in Google Scholar
Jardine, Lisa. The Curious Life of Robert Hooke, the Man who Measured London. London: Harper Collins, 2003.Search in Google Scholar
Jardine, Lisa. “Robert Hooke: A Reputation Restored.” In Robert Hooke: Tercentennial Studies, edited by Michel Cooper, Michael Hunter, 247–58. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.Search in Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre. Études Galiléennes. Paris: Hermann, 1939.Search in Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre. From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1957.Search in Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre. La Révolution Astronomique: Copernic, Kepler, Borelli. Paris: Hermann, 1961.Search in Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre. Newtonian Studies. London: Chapman & Hall, 1965.10.4159/harvard.9780674181861Search in Google Scholar
Nauenberg, Michael. “Robert Hooke’s Seminal Contributions to Orbital Dynamics.” Physics in Perspective 7 (2005), 4–34.10.1007/s00016-004-0226-ySearch in Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy, edited by I. B. Cohen, R. E. Shoefield. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, 1958.Search in Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, edited by H. W. Turnbull, J. F. Scott, A. R. Hall, and L. Tilling, 7 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1959–1977.10.1017/9781108651820Search in Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. The Mathematical Papers of Isaac Newton, edited by Derek Tom Whiteside, 8 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967–1981.Search in Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. The Optical Papers of Isaac Newton. Vol. 1. The Optical Lectures 1670–1672, edited by Alan E. Shapiro. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984Search in Google Scholar
Pappus. Mathematicae Collectiones à Federico Commandino Urbinate in Latinum Conversae, et Commentariis Illustratae. Pesaro: Girolamo Concordia, 1588.Search in Google Scholar
Pugliese, Patri. “Robert Hooke and the Dynamics of Motion in a Curved Path.” In Robert Hooke, New Studies, edited by Michael Hunter, Simon Schaffer, 181–205. Woodbridge: The Boydell Press, 1989.Search in Google Scholar
Rossi, Paolo. Un altro presente: saggi sulla storia della filosofia. Bologna: Il Mulino, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven. “The Invisible Technician.” American Scientist 77 (1989a), 554–63.Search in Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven. “Who Was Robert Hooke?” In Robert Hooke, New Studies, edited by Michael Hunter and Simon Schaffer, 253–85. Woodbridge: The Boydell Press, 1989b.Search in Google Scholar
Shapiro, Barbara J. Probability and Certainty in Seventeenth-Century England: A Study of the Relationships Between Natural Science, Religion, History, Law and Literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983.Search in Google Scholar
Sprat, Thomas. The History of the Royal Society of London, for the Improving of Natural Knowledge. London: T. R. [Roycroft] for J. Martyn and J. Allestry, 1667.Search in Google Scholar
Stewart, Larry. “Science, Instruments, and Guilds in Early-Modern Britain.” Early Science and Medicine 10:3 (2005), 392–410.10.1163/1573382054615433Search in Google Scholar
Tournès, Dominique. La Construction Tractionnelle des Équations Différentielles. Paris: Blanchard, 2009.Search in Google Scholar
Van Schooten, Frans. De Organica Conicarum Sectionum in Plano Descriptione Tractatus: Geometris, Opticis, Praesertim Vero Gnomonicis & Mechanicis Utilis. Leiden: ex Officina Elzeviriorum, 1646.Search in Google Scholar
Vickers, Brian. English Science, Bacon to Newton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.Search in Google Scholar
Wang, Xioana. ‘Though their Causes be not yet discover’d’ Occult Principles in the Making of Newton’s Natural Philosophy, PhD thesis, Edinburgh, 2019.Search in Google Scholar
© 2020 Niccolò Guicciardini, published by De Gruyter
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.