Abstract
Is there a political theology of revolution in Carl Schmitt or is his political theology only and exclusively autocratic? Schmitt sees the key to revolutionary politics in the construction of the idea of the people as a constituent power. This idea, and the first event it produced, namely, the French Revolution, not only establishes a concrete state of exception but also makes exceptionality both at the same time a constituent and a de-constituent element of the political order of the Modern State. The exception goes from coming from “outside” the political order to being integrated into it as an element of stasis, that is to say, of destabilization. Hence, all modern politics, under the mask of legality, become permanently revolutionary. This article analyses the juridical genealogy and the theological–political transfers involved in the construction of the modern revolutionary political era that follows from Schmitt’s insights.
Is there a political theology of revolution in Carl Schmitt or is his political theology only and exclusively autocratic? This article offers a nuanced approach to the question. While in Schmitt’s early writings, revolutionary political theology appears linked to the idea of the constituent power of the people, discovered by Sieyès – mainly attributed to Spinoza and Malebranche – in his later writings, the revolutionary political possibilities are opened up by Gnosticism and pagan polytheism. To address this complex question, we first approach the problem as Schmitt does in his early writings through the analysis of the constituent power of the people and its theological–political interpretation, and then, we direct our attention to contemporary possibilities of a political theology of revolution.
1 The Problem: State of Exception and Democracy
In the preface to the fourth edition of 1978 of his Dictatorship, Schmitt makes note of the significant increase at that time in the number of works on the question of the state of exception in the law. He attributes it to the fact that crises have become both integrating and disintegrating elements of anomalous intermediate situations between war and peace. One of the main theses of this article is that this sentence reveals an important interpretative key to understanding what Schmitt considers to be a revolutionary democracy. Indeed, in this text from his early writings, the German jurist notes that the exception has become, through the idea of the constituent power of the people, that is of the people as the sovereign subject at the origin of every constitution, an integrating element of political order, which operates as a revolutionary device.
Dictatorship (1921) traced the history of the idea of dictatorship as a state of exception from the beginnings of modern thought on sovereignty to the proletarian class struggle. While not ignoring, of course, exceptional situations in antiquity,[1] Schmitt was most interested in the political conceptualization of modernity and devoted his best efforts to it. In Dictatorship, the state of exception is initially linked to the modern concept of dictatorship, that is to the possibility of the suspension of the existing legal order by a political decision that seeks to impose a new order or to restore an order that has begun to weaken due to historical circumstances.[2]
Many different interpretations have been given to Dictatorship. In the brief biography that appears as the first chapter of my The Political Discourse of Carl Schmitt, I have pointed out that this book opens a series of books like Political Theology or The Concept of the Political among others, which I characterize as the “discovery of the political spirit.” In these books, Schmitt develops a theory of the sovereign decision, after some more general works on literature and law.[3] This is how Mc Cormick or Scheuerman sees Dictatorship, without placing particular emphasis on his comments on constituent power, but rather on Schmitt’s struggle against liberalism at the expense of democracy.[4] However, there has also been a growing literature that has pointed to the importance of this early work of Schmitt in awakening interest in the idea of constituent power. One cannot forget Klein’s judgement in his theory of constituent power that Schmitt was responsible for the renewal of the idea of constituent power in the jurisprudence of his time.[5] Rubinelli also notes that Schmitt represents a turning point in the history of constituent power by placing him “in the middle of the story … equating constituent power with his understanding of sovereignty as the power of the elected leader to take unbounded and ultimate decisions, through the institutional structure of the state.”[6]
Also the interpretations of Breuer, Cristi, Kalyvas, and Arato are relevant in this aspect. All of them indicate the importance of the idea of constituent power for the development of Schmitt’s resignification of the theory of democracy in his Constitutional Theory. They all recognize how Schmitt uses the theory of constituent power to his advantage, domesticating it. But they also seem to forget that Schmitt is critical of this theory up to the end, even though, in political modernity, in which the only form of legitimation is democratic legitimacy, the theory of constituent power is the only theoretical instrument that allows for a non-masked presence of political power that should be distinguished and limited by legality.[7]
Schmitt never loses sight of the revolutionary and destabilizing possibilities of the theory of the constituent power, precisely those that were put into practice in the French Revolution. In the first place, its absolute character, which can be glimpsed by extracting the particular genealogy – that is a way of reading political ideas and concepts that are not immediately given by its history[8] – of the idea of constituent power that Schmitt builds at the time that describes the history of dictatorships. This aspect has not been dealt with in the cited bibliography, which has made a different reading of this book.[9] But, secondly, the particular stasis that the idea of the constituent power puts at the heart of every political order. For this exegesis, Schmitt uses the particular methodology that would be the subject of his publication a year later, Political Theology. That is to say, interpreting the idea of constituent power from its most radical conceptualization, that is from the metaphysical and theological implications of Malebrache and Spinoza’s philosophy. It is this radical conceptualization that will allow Schmitt to resignificate the idea of pouvoir constituent of Sieyès, revealing its most revolutionary possibilities. The opposition of both philosophers to the dualist mechanisms of Descartes and Hobbes will lead Schmitt to a more general political theology of revolution in Political Theology II. Although authors such as Koekkoek and Negri have highlighted the importance that Spinoza’s metaphysics has in Schmitt’s interpretation of constituent power, they have not connected this idea with the political theology of revolution that appears at the end of Political Theology II.[10] Many others, however, disconnected Schmitt’s ideas about constituent power from his theological political positions, as, for example in Cristi, who affirms that Schmitt refuses a theological interpretation of democracy,[11] or as with Breuer, who thinks of Schmitt’s political theology only in terms of the Hobbesian theological political approach.[12]
This article sets aside the systematic place of Dictatorship (1921) concerning other texts of Schmitt’s work, such as Political Theology (1922) and Constitutional Theory (1928). While McCormick sees Political Theology as a radicalization of Schmitt’s thesis in Dictatorship, defending a rightist mass-democratic conception,[13] Cristi and Kalyvas observe the continuity between Dictatorship and Constitutional Theory. Both recognize that Schmitt very early in his production perceives the need to find a modern legitimation for politics, that is of democracy and he views it through the theoretical lens of constituent power. He soon realizes that he must abandon Hobbes’ path. Magalhaes for his part characterizes Schmitt as a populist. For Magalhaes, the systematic introduction of this concept in Schmitt’s Constitutional Theory is perhaps “the single most important reason why many left-radical democratic theorists have been fascinated by his work.”[14]
Indeed, it is in Political Theology that the connection to the political theology of sovereignty that the exception appears most clearly characterized: “The exception in jurisprudence is analogous to the miracle in theology.”[15] From here stems the countless misunderstandings that have systematically crept into most commentaries on Schmitt’s work, namely, that Schmitt’s political theology is a political theology of authoritarian personalist absolute sovereignty in line with Hobbes. As Schmitt rightly comments in his The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes, for a radical decisionist like Hobbes – who had enacted the decisive auctoritas non veritas turn, nothing is true – everything is a command: “A miracle is what that sovereign state authority commands its subjects to believe to be a miracle.”[16] We cannot forget when reading this sentence that the Stuarts, in particular Charles II, were engaged in the practice of royal miracle healings. Charles II, between 1660 and 1664, touched approximately 23,000 people with his royal hand, as Schmitt underlines. Although he originally takes the example of the miracle from Donoso Cortés, in his Discourse on the Dictatorship of 4 January 1849, Schmitt himself points out in the book Dictatorship, “It has been argued that dictatorship is a miracle, on the grounds that its suspension of state laws is comparable with the suspension of natural laws in miracles. In reality, dictatorship is not this miracle; it is a breaking up of the legal system that is implicit in such a newly established dominion.”[17] And in Political Theology, he asserts, “Only by being aware of this analogy can we appreciate the manner in which the philosophical ideas of the state developed in the last centuries.”[18]
The analogy appears to Schmitt as a method, which he calls the “sociology of juristic concepts,” consisting of “radical conceptualization, a consistent thinking that is pushed into metaphysics and theology.”[19] He sees Leibniz as one of the great defenders of this logic of political analysis in that he emphasizes the systematic relationship between jurisprudence and theology, rejecting, however, a comparison of jurisprudence with medicine and mathematics. However, in his opinion, all literature from the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, including Rousseau, is full of such analogies.[20]
At least since Hobbes, political theology’s definition of sovereignty must be attributed to the position of the monarch in the Modern State, yet we cannot assume that it is a normative definition for Schmitt. Thus, the political theology of the authoritarian regal state sovereignty should not so much be ascribed to Schmitt as to the political thought of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Schmitt’s political position depends on the theology and metaphysics of a later era, at the very moment when in his Constitutional Theory he seeks a new democratic foundation for political legitimacy.
Kalyvas is the one who has better analysed the constituent parts of Schmitt’s theory of democracy.[21] He does so by distinguishing three moments: Firstly, the founding moment, in which Schmitt shifted from a traditional notion of sovereignty as the ultimate command to the idea of sovereignty as the creative and founding will of the constituent subject. Secondly, the constitutional order, in which Schmitt confronted the problem of the self-enforcement and self-limitation of the democratic order. At this moment, the relevant distinction is between the constitution and constitutional laws. The constitution is the incarnation and institutionalization of the constituent will and of the substantive values to which it has given birth. As Vinx has argued, Schmitt is one of the authors that have defended the claim that material limits to constitutional amendment need not be democratically illegitimate.[22] Thirdly, the moment of the extraparliamentary sovereign, which recovers the power of sovereignty in times of crisis. With this strategy, well described in my view by Kalyvas, Schmitt adapts Sieyès’ theory of constituent power to his normative interests, disregarding, as Breuer points out, the more liberal aspects of Sieyès.[23]
Notwithstanding Kalyvas’ aforementioned observations (re: the place of the theory of constituent power in Schmitt’s work), this article primarily examines the extent to which Schmitt’s theological–political interpretation in Dictatorship uncovers the most revolutionary possibilities of democratic theory, to the point of attributing these very possibilities to modernity itself, and the ways in which this interpretation could be extended to a general political theology of revolution.
In several texts, Schmitt describes the modern political condition as the impossibility of escaping democracy, as the political condition in which the only possible sovereign is the people. It is the case of Constitutional Theory where he largely describes democracy as the political component of the modern constitution,[24] as well as in Political Theology where he asserts:
Since 1848 the theory of public law has become ‘positive,’ and behind this word is usually hidden its dilemma; or the theory has propounded in different paraphrases the idea that all power resides in the pouvoir constituant of the people, which means that the democratic notion of legitimacy has replaced the monarchical. It was therefore an occurrence of utmost significance that Donoso Cortés, one of the foremost representatives of decisionist thinking and a Catholic philosopher of the state, one who was intensely conscious of the metaphysical kernel of all politics, concluded in reference to the revolution of 1848, that the epoch of royalism was at an end.[25]
Indeed, this article sets aside the exception understood as an exception to the law which, although without breaking legal continuity, is considered “external” to the existing order and therefore preserves a certain clear dialectic between normality and exceptionality. Schmitt affirms this in his description of commissarial dictatorship and even in the theory of constituent power which Schmitt himself develops in Constitutional Theory. Rather, the article examines the most radical interpretation of the idea of constituent power by Schmitt in which the exception is constituted as the keystone of political normality itself, insofar as it not only does not break the legal continuity but also acts within it as a device for the self-alteration of society or as a permanent state of exception.
Schmitt makes a clear distinction between these two ways of understanding the exception when he points out the significant difference between considering dictatorship a “state of exception” outside of all that counts as normal – of democracy, of liberal principles, of the constitution – and a state whose entire existing order can be called dictatorship: “Another change in the meaning of dictatorship occurs when not only the contested political order but also the intended government is called a dictatorship, as happens in the communist literature.”[26] This draws out Schmitt’s criticism.
He posits that this state is called a sovereign dictatorship, because a whole state is a tool for transforming a given political order into another political reality, and its justification is based on a norm that is no longer purely political nor grounded in simple legal positivism; rather, its legitimacy is founded on a philosophy of history: “Whoever is on the side of the things to come is allowed to push against what is already collapsing.”[27] However, Dictatorship concludes by saying that the dictatorship of the proletariat presupposes the concept of a sovereign dictatorship, as it was at the heart of the French National Convention’s theory and practice.[28]
To think of both French and Soviet revolutionary politics as sovereign dictatorships means admitting that the exception lies at the heart of their politics. As he points out in The Leviathan in the Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes: “The periodic revival of the national convention as an eternal natural right (Naturrecht) was to him (Rousseau) a natural occurrence; in other words, he allowed for the incorporation of the Revolution, as it were, into the configuration of the State.”[29]
From that moment on, all politics are possible permanent revolutions under the mask of stability. In his view, this new historical circumstance is inescapable. The political structure of modernity alters the position of the exception and, with it, the meaning of all political concepts shifts. Although he uses the concept of constituent power in a “moderate” way in his Constitutional Theory, as the aforementioned scholars have shown, the most radical theological–political interpretation is possible and is connected by Schmitt to radical forms of democracy such as Sorel’s anarchist theory of power.[30]
In fact, the seventeenth century was dominated by this idea of the sole sovereign: “In the theory of the state of the seventeenth century, the monarch is identified with God and has in the state a position exactly analogous to that attributed to God in the Cartesian system of the world.”[31] He continues, “A continuous thread runs through the metaphysical, political, and sociological conceptions that postulate the sovereign as a personal unit and primeval creator.”[32] However, the idea of constituent power that surfaced in Sieyès’ political theory, and the exception it introduces in the heart of the political realm, coexisted with another metaphysical, political, and sociological constellation.
The discussion thus far now brings us to address our main issues of Schmitt’s genealogy of constituent power and its connection to a political–theological theory. These two issues have been neglected in the relevant literature: the first is elaborated mainly in Dictatorship, but partly also in Constitutional Theory – which explains the absolute character of constituent power that opens the door to the more radically revolutionary possibilities of democracy as a sovereign dictatorship – and the second, his genealogy’s link to a political–theological perspective, that is from the metaphysical and theological implications of the metaphysics and theology of Spinoza and Malebranche. These areas of focus open up other possibilities for a political theology of revolution.
For the sake of clarity, the article will: (1) Firstly, address Schmitt’s genealogical construction, which comes to explain why the constituent power of the people is absolute in the theory of democracy that is put into practice in revolutionary France. Indeed, Schmitt constructs a genealogy of the constituent power when recounting the history of dictatorship or states of exception. Like any genealogy, it is a theoretical construction that shows a possible reading of the concepts and not the particular reading that Sieyès himself might have made. In any case, this reading is possible for any contemporary reader who wants to redefine the idea of the constituent power of the people. This is precisely what Schmitt does. In Dictatorship, Schmitt postulates that in principle the concept of constituent power is eminently juridical. However, he shows that it is interwoven with theological–political transfers, which give it its radical character. (2) Secondly, the article makes explicit the theological–political question at the heart of the radical interpretation of the theory of constituent power in its radical version. (3) Thirdly, the article examines the political theology of revolution that Schmitt offers in Political Theology II.
2 Constituent Power as a Re-Signification of Absolutism
The conceptual fiction of the people’s constituent power is consolidated through certain conceptual milestones that, in Schmitt’s genealogy, include the idea of power established in canon law with the figure of papal plenitudo potestatis; the idea of extraordinary oaths that establish the literature of the arcana; the idea of the persona ficta that Hobbes sketches in his Leviathan; Montesquieu’s idea of balance; and, finally, Sieyès’ revolutionary construction of constituent power as unlimited power and its transformation into Robespierre’s revolutionary practice. These all help to explain how the absolute character of revolutionary democracy has come to be conceived.
Following these milestones, Schmitt seems aware of the strictly juridical character of the emergence of the concept.[33] Yet, when it comes to the relevant genealogy, very different theological–political transfers have intervened; they cannot be simply summarized with a phrase such as the transformation of God’s absolute power into a sovereign people’s absolute power, as Schmitt himself seems to summarize with a phrase in his Constitutional Theory that he attributes to Althusius.[34]
Schmitt points out in Dictatorship that transformation of the medieval order into the Modern State is based on a central milestone found in the fact that reform of ecclesiastical organization hinged on the figure of papal plenitudo potestatis, which was slowly built up in the late Middle Ages. Generally, this concept is traced back to the metaphysically rooted distinction between potestas dei absoluta and ordinate.[35] Schmitt, however, does not refer to it explicitly, but rather focuses on the juridical idea of plenitudo potestatis papalis. It is true that, in Dictatorship, Schmitt does not emphasize the absolute character of political power as much as he does in Political Theology or in Constitutional Theory; rather, there, focuses on the destruction of intermediate powers carried out by the construction of the plenitudo potestatis papalis. Papal sovereignty, shielded by this expression, was a pioneer in the construction of absolute power since, by the thirteenth century, it had already far surpassed the medieval feudal organization, something that happened in the civil sphere much later. Starting with Innocent III, papal power was essentially seen as the pope acting as the sole lord of the Church rather than as its supreme feudal lord. The prelates ceased to be his vassals to become his functionaries, as Schmitt notes, “What was perceived as revolutionary in plenitudo potestatis was the termination of the medieval idea of an unconditional hierarchy of function. This hierarchy could not have been changed, not even by the highest authority, and every function holder could lay claim to it.”[36]
It is not so much the possible arbitrariness of the content of the decision that threatens the order of power, but the suppression of the very hierarchical institutionality of the Church in which the pope was simply a primus inter pares. In Schmitt’s opinion, the practice of papal government offers many varied examples of commissarial activity, taken particularly from the time of the schism when Antipope Boniface IX (1389–1404) and his successor Urban VI governed the Church and, due to extraordinary circumstances, adopted exceptional measures.[37] The specific character of the commissarial figure as shown in papal practice consists in the fact that to achieve certain ends, legitimately acquired rights and formal legal precepts can be dispensed with. This commissarial figure, who acts as a mediator of absolute sovereign power, became conceptually decisive in the revolutionary events of 1789.
The second major milestone that contributed to the slow conceptual elaboration of the idea of constituent power refers to the abundant literature produced since the beginning of the Renaissance on the idea of raison d’état. In his opinion, these texts deepen the perception of the acquisition and maintenance of political power as a technique associated with the realm of facticity. However, he adds, “of greater significance than the vague ideas of raison d’état and salus publica [public health], which can be easily moralised from the position of a certain understanding of the state, is the concept of the political arcanum [‘secret’], which we find at the centre of this kind of political literature.”[38]
As the most obvious example, Schmitt refers to Arnoldius Clapmarius De Arcanis Rerum publicanorum libri 6, 1641. Clapmarius refers the expression to Tacitus, who in Annales II, 36 (115–117) speaks of the arcana imperii to characterize Tiberius’ cunning policy. All sciences use their wiles to achieve their ends, and the same is true of politics. On top of these realities, certain decorative institutions are established to help justify political actions. Schmitt’s citation of Clapmarius and Besold, rather than of ancient authors, suggests that, rather than an inveterate practice, the politics of secrets was inaugurated with the Modern State. Moreover, Schmitt intends to point out as a novelty that this practice is juridified with the emergence of the Modern State.[39] The early modern literature of the arcana is in Schmitt’s view juristic. Clapmarius distinguishes within arcana between arcana imperii and arcana dominationis, the former referring to the power of the state in its normal situation of existence, i.e. in normal times, and the latter to the power exercised in the protection and defence of people in extraordinary times of political instability. A dictatorship would therefore be an arcanum dominationis. Jean Bodin’s Six Books of the Republic (1576) already listed the jura dominationis to circumscribe the power of the sovereign power, defined in the sixth book as the absolute and perpetual power of a republic to limit power. However, as Schmitt points out in Clapmarius that the arcana dominationis appears as unlimited power to do whatever the situation demands, albeit secretively. In his Conclusiones de jure publico, Clapmarius identifies arcana dominationis with the reason of state and defines it as recta et secreta privilegia conservandae dominationis introducta boni publici causa.[40] In other words, it is a power dictated by necessity to maintain jura dominationis. Thus, the question of sovereignty shifts from jura dominationis, as they appeared in Bodin, to the question of the jura extraordinaria, which Clapmarius calls arcana dominationis. Behind ordained power lies an undefined power that may or may not be expressed, depending on the need.
The arcana literature reflects that public law cannot be treated the same as private law. In private law, aequitas and justitia govern; in public law, salus publica prevails. In Clapmarius, as Schmitt notes, the state of exception appears as legitimate tyranny: “[I]t refers in principle to the legally unlimited exercise of power that was entitled to intervene in the existing order of law and in the existing functions and acquired rights.”[41] The central point here is that whoever holds the plenitude of power always decides for himself whether or not a case of exception arises, and hence its absolute character. Although the imagining of an unlimited power in principle, as popularized in the arcana literature, was a relevant milestone that influenced the construction of the revolutionary pouvoir constituent, it is important to bear in mind Schmitt’s assertion in Constitutional Theory that, until the French Revolution, no prince had been the absolute subject of constituent power, something that did, however, occur later during the monarchical restoration, after the “revolutionary turn of power.”[42]
At this point, the multitudo dissoluta enters the scene with Hobbes’ theory of the absolute state. Schmitt does not seem to attach much importance to it in the genealogy he sketches in Dictatorship, barely referring to Hobbes on this occasion and only pointing out that Hobbes’ construction points to the question of sovereign dictatorship.[43] In his view, Hobbes still understands the populus as a person and not simply as a formless mob. For Schmitt, as he suggests in The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes, the mechanical order of the state is not so much the remedy for the multitude, but for revolution.[44] However, the artificiality of the political person is central to the modern construction of the idea of the people, as Schmitt also noted when speaking of the mechanical aspect of the state.[45] The state, the sovereign, represents this multitude, which becomes an artificial single subject, a people, through the words and actions of a natural person because, as Schmitt makes definitively clear, only a natural person can decide and act. In other words, the representative acts on behalf of the multitude such that the latter is no longer formless.[46] Indeed, the representative logic of the Modern State opens the way with its distinction between author and actor: the person is the actor, while the author owns the words and actions.[47] At the very moment when the people appear as a unit of action, they are endowed with the same absolute power as the political sovereign. In other words, the coetus populi always remains sovereign.[48] This idea is one of Hobbes’ great theoretical novelties, and it became central to Schmitt’s genealogy of constituent power in Dictatorship. It moves away from the medieval world’s understanding of political community as a status and begins to understand it as a pact of association among all with all according to each party’s interests. It is not just a matter of one individual being able to perform another individual’s actions, but of one individual being able to perform a multitude’s actions. This opens up revolutionary theoretical possibilities.
Like Marsilius and Gerson’s conciliar theory tried to assert itself against the pope’s plenitudo potestatis, locating fullness of power in the Church, in the political sphere, Schmitt similarly views the German estates’ opposition to imperial power.[49] Montesquieu, in Schmitt’s opinion, takes advantage of this idea when he points out that “the law needed a mediating institution through which governmental power could flow so that an arbitrary and spontaneous expression of the will of the state would be prevented.”[50] The idea of counterbalancing intermediate powers is behind the concept of balance, mistranslated, in his opinion, as equilibrium. Balance is the mediation of plenitudo potestatis. The immediate exercise of state omnipotence is despotism. The old medieval idea of the intermediation of power re-emerged in another form, that of the balance of power, which was then gradually transformed into the fiction of a general will.
Indeed, the sovereign is no longer the institution of the people, as it appears in Hobbes, and instead fundamentally becomes a will, the volonté général. In Rousseau’s Contrat social, the absolute power that Hobbes assigned to the sovereign is transferred to the people, who alone can mobilize legislation.[51] The idea of general will implies two other new features for political power. First, the volonté général is the will of the sovereign and constitutes the state as a unit – it is divine will expressed in legislation. Second, people are good by nature and, therefore, according to his conception, are good in all things.[52] Only those who are morally good and free have the right to be called a people. If the majority has fallen into corruption, then the virtuous minority can employ all the means of power necessary to aid virtue’s triumph. The terror exercised by this minority cannot be called coercion; it is just how the unfree egoist attains his true self-will, awakening in him the citoyen.[53] Hence, as Schmitt points out, his proposal necessarily depends on an enlightened philosophy,[54] in line with which Rousseau praises the figure of the legislator.[55] This figure appears foreign to the will of the people, but it is central to Rousseau’s democratic theory. The general will is always right, however, the judgement that guides it is not always enlightened. Limits to the power of the people are set by the sage, i.e. the implementation of rationality without passions. Thus, the idea of the people in Rousseau is trapped in a kind of aporia. On the one hand, it is always what it must be, but, on the other hand, it can only be achieved by the action of the legislator. For Rousseau, however, the republic’s true constitution is engraved in the hearts of its citizens.[56] Apart from the legislator’s intervention, people direct what they do and want; acting to achieve the end that corresponds to the will of the people means acting exclusively and at all times on a commissarial basis. The will of the people cannot be delegated or represented, much less can a right to exercise that will exist. Thus, Schmitt points out: “Nothing proves Rousseau’s belief in the absolutism of the state more than this: the transformation – which dominates all his ideas – of the entire institutional activity of the state into an arbitrary, revocable and unconditionally dependent commissarial operation.”[57] Certainly, the legislator is not a commissar, but rather a wise and eminent man who projects wise law, but sanctioning this law is the sole responsibility of the volonté générale. And this sanctioning takes place in a free plebiscite.[58]
In Schmitt’s view, the conjunction of these ideas comes to forge the idea of pouvoir constituant:
When a relationship emerges that makes it possible to give the legislator the power of a dictator, to create a dictatorial legislator and constitutional dictator, then the commissary dictatorship has become a sovereign dictatorship. This relationship will come about through an idea that is, in its substance, a consequence of Rousseau’s Contrat social, although he does not name as a separate power: le pouvoir constituant [the constituting power].[59]
The notion of constituent power was developed by Sieyès, particularly in his work on the third estate.[60] According to it, all existing powers are subject to the validity of laws, rules, and forms, which they cannot modify on their own since their existence is based on the Constitution. Yet, at the same time, there must be some foundational power to the constitution and its actual enactment, which, in principle, is unlimited because it is not subject to the constitution and does not disappear with it. Sieyès’ theory is only comprehensible as an attempt to find the unorganizable organizer, says Schmitt.[61] The nation only has rights, not obligations; the constituted power, on the other hand, only has obligations, not rights. Sieyès links this to the admissibility of representation. In fact, he conceived of the deputies of the Constituent Assembly of 1789 as representatives, not as holders of an imperative mandate. If this is so, then a strange relationship arises between representatives and the omnipotent constituent will. Hence, Schmitt stresses that representation can be nothing other than unconditional commissarial action: “The commissary dictator is the unconditional commissar of action of a pouvoir constitué, and sovereign dictatorship is the unconditional commission of action of a pouvoir constituant.”[62]
The National Convention that met on September 20, 1792 was tasked with drafting a Constitution (June 24, 1793). Once completed and accepted by the people in a plebiscite, the convention’s commission was fulfilled, its powers ended, and it was dissolved. Because of the war context and counter-revolutionary movement, on October 10, 1793, the convention resolved that the provisional government of France would be “revolutionary” until peace was achieved. To this end, the Constitution of 1793 was suspended and did not come into force again. In February 1793, the commissioners of the National Convention were officially invested with pouvoirs ilimités. They acted by appealing to the constituent power of the people. Barère urged the establishment of a Comité de salut public, which acted as a commission of the National Convention. In fact, with the creation of the Comité de salut publique, the activity of the individual commissaries was controlled by a more centralized organization. It was not, however, the only Committee.[63] All authorities and civil servants were placed under the immediate supervision of the Comité de salut public and the Comité de s û reté générale. The Comité de salut public appointed the revolutionary committees, which had police powers. With the Commissaires’ network, the existing order of the state was replaced by a new order of plural command, completely centralized and without any autonomy, i.e. according to dictatorial logic. Indeed, Robespierre dominated the Committee and the latter dominated the Convention. On December 4, 1793, the government of the revolution issued a provisional Constitution, the fundamental precept of which was: “la convention nationale est le centre unique de l’impulsion du gouvernement.”
In the light of revolutionary events, Schmitt radical interpretation of Sieyès notion of constituent power is linked to the idea of a sovereign dictatorship.[64] It entails unlimited power in principle insofar as it is unlawful. But, at the same time, what is constituted is always de-constituting itself, at least as a possibility, insofar as constituent power remains a key element of the whole political edifice.
As Schmitt later points out in Constitutional Theory, the 1789 revolution’s “mental assumption” corresponds to the theory of constituent power. Constituent power presupposes the people as an existential political entity. The word “nation,” he notes, expressively designates a people capable of action, awakened to political consciousness.[65] Schmitt distinguishes the English tradition from the French one on this point precisely in Constitutional Theory. Historically, the idea of the people as a unit of action prevalent on the continent depends on absolute monarchies’ concentration of power, whereas, in the English revolutions, it only appears as a presupposition facilitated by an insular territorial constitution.[66]
In 1789, the people constituted themselves as the subject of constituent power and gave themselves a constitution based on an assumption of political unity and capacity to act. This was already a fundamentally political decision, Schmitt argues.[67] The collective political “being” precedes the constitution. Absolute power moves from the executive to the people, but the former by no means disappears.
In short, maximum extension of jura dominationis comes from the doctrine of constituent power as carried out in revolutionary practice in eighteenth-century France. It is not for nothing that Schmitt himself points out, in The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, that Bolshevism and Caesarisms can be more democratic than some democracies. That is to say, as pointed out at the beginning, the dictatorship of the proletariat is just a new way of expressing French revolutionary theory.
It is indeed difficult to connect dialectical development and dictatorship, because dictatorship seems to be an interruption of the continual series of development, a mechanical intervention in organic evolution. Development and dictatorship seem to be mutually exclusive. The unending process of a world spirit that develops itself in contradictions must also include within itself even its own real contradiction, dictatorship, and thus rob it of its essence, decision. Development goes on without a break and even interruptions must serve it as negations so that it will be pushed further. The essential point is that an exception never comes from outside into the immanence of development.[68]
For both, the national and proletariat revolution, the exception no longer originates “outside” the political order, but rather becomes immanent. While the French Revolution is largely considered a violent outburst, it consolidates a model that can change perpetually through constituent – and never constituted – power that has the potential to desire new things at every moment and on a whim. Here, we find the model for the sovereign dictatorship found in mass democracies.
This absolutization of power, however, corresponds not to the medieval metaphysics of God’s omnipotence, but rather to another kind of theological–political idea.
3 Spinocism and Malebranchism at the Heart of Revolutionary Democracy
Schmitt uncovers several theological–metaphysical conceptions in the construction of the idea of the constituent power, which, combined with the juridical idea of unlimited power and with the political imagination of the French Revolution, make revolutionary democracy possible as a dispositif – using a Foucauldian expression – for modern politics.
Mika Ojakangas has argued that the idea of constituent power is not a secularized theological concept, since Schmitt’s idea of constituent power, unlike Sieyès’, has the absolute character that none of the theological or canonical constructions that might have been part of his genealogical construction ever had. He has in mind the idea of the Medieval divina omnipotentia. [69] Ojakangas, however, never refers to Schmitt’s theological–political construction of the concept of constituent power in Dictatorship, which, as already announced, depends on another metaphysical and theological worldview, different from the medieval one.
Far from medieval theological conceptions, the ideas of an unlimited and never definitively constituted power and the idea of the general will of the people are shown to be the key pieces of a politics of permanent revolution. Looking at them from the perspective of what Schmitt himself calls the sociology of juridical concepts in Political Theology, we realise that these two theoretical pieces carry with them the logical remains of two distinct metaphysical–theological models, the Spinozian and the Malebranchian; just as, in Schmitt’s view, the construction of the Hobbesian Leviathan was a transfer of the Cartesian idea of the animated machine.[70]
Indeed, the relationship between constituent power and constituted power has its main analogue in Spinozian metaphysics with the relationship between natura naturans and natura naturata, which is already an organic idea.[71] However, much Spinoza may consider himself a rationalist, this theory shows, in Schmitt’s opinion, that he is not so much so.[72] The theory of constituent power is also organic and dynamic and not mechanistic: “The theory of the pouvoir constituant is incomprehensible simply as a form of mechanistic rationalism. The people, the nation, the primordial force of any state – these always constitute new organs.”[73] Schmitt had already reflected in Political Romanticism on the possible mystical interpretation of Spinozism as a basis for the unorganisierbar Organisierende.[74] The amorphous power of the people, as de natura naturans, is prior to the unity of the constitution as the natura naturata.
If the idea of an unlimited and never definitively constituted power depends to a large extent on the Spinozian metaphysical imaginary, in Schmitt’s opinion, the idea of the general will comes from Malebranche’s metaphysical imaginary. Both ideas are combined in Schmitt’s interpretation of the constituent power in order to construct a metaphysical foundation for revolutionary democracy.
As Schmitt points out, Malebranche detested Spinoza’s pantheism and protested against it on the grounds that it placed truth or nomological necessity above even the personal God.[75] But Malebranche himself cannot escape the result that the personal God is transformed also into a general order of nature. He makes God into a general order that occurs in complete harmony and in which even the efficacy of grace follows in a nomological fashion. If Descartes sees the basis of moral laws in the will of God, Malebranche thinks that moral laws constitute an eternal order that not even God can alter. In the Malebranchian doctrine, God possesses nothing but a volonté générale, and any particularity is alien to his nature. In Schmitt’s opinion, eighteenth-century France politicized this metaphysical and scientific concept of law to the extent that the State is only allowed to establish universal and abstract rules in the form of laws.[76]
Indeed, Malebranche points out that there must be occasional causes that set general laws in motion, otherwise they would have to be set in motion by God, and that could only happen by a volonté particulière [particular will]. The idea that only God has a volonté générale et immutable [general and immutable will] and that every volonté particulière subverts his dignity is, in his view, a commonplace idea in eighteenth-century France. Schmitt points out, “One must grasp this metaphysics to understand the argument of the Contrat social.”[77]
Indeed, Malebranche’s occasionalism, in Schmitt’s view, succeeds in setting the Cartesian dualist scheme in motion without actually resolving it. In the occasionalist resolution of the Cartesian problem of the relationship between mind and body, God becomes the cause of both mental and physical events, and of the interactions between them. Occasionalism does not clear up this dualism and rather lets it stand, albeit in an illusory way by shifting into a comprehensive third sphere, namely, God’s occasional action. Interest simply shifts from a dualistic result into a more general, “higher” and “true” unity. The occasionalist God essentially functions as true reality in which the opposition between body and soul disappears into the domain of the unreal.[78] When it comes to a theory of the person and a philosophical account of human action, this means that it is not the human being who acts, but rather God, for whom the person is only an occasion. The world itself becomes nothing more than contingent material for God’s action, which reflects true reality.
From Schmitt’s point of view, Malebranchian nomological logic combines well with Spinoza’s pantheism of a nature always under construction and never definitively constructed, much to Malebranche’s regret. This is made clear in Political Romanticism, when he asserts that the occasionalist logic, stripped of its metaphysics, appears as a combination of antitheses that resolve themselves to perform whatever action is required. “No concept retains its form. Everything dissolves into an oratorical music.”[79]
Indeed, for Schmitt, the new forms of nineteenth-century revolutionary politics are also derived from the metaphysical presuppositions of the eighteenth century. In Schmitt’s account, the Romantic movement retains the basic metaphysical attitude of Malebranchian occasionalism differently as Rousseau did it. Although, indeed, Rousseau can already be considered a Romantic.
With the collapse of the traditional idea of God, the eighteenth-century philosophers raised the question of what could take its place as the fundamental metaphysical principle. Two new ontological aspirants or demiurges made a claim to this status: humanity, or the “revolutionary god,” conceived of as the people, the general will, the public, or society; and history, the “conservative god,” conceived of as cultures, traditions, and nations.[80] The latter constitutes the general human community as historically concretized people, which become a sociological and historical reality by means of this delimitation and acquire the capacity to produce a particular law and a particular language in the expression of an individual national spirit. Therefore, what a people is “organically” and what the Volksgeist signifies can only be ascertained historically. In addition, in romantic political theology, the people are not their own master, as in Rousseau’s account, but rather the result of historical development. The idea of arbitrary power over history is a real romantic revolutionary idea. It “fabricates” whatever it wants and is able to create itself.[81]
In Schmitt’s view, the 1789 revolution was a bourgeois revolution against the aristocracy, although, by 1792, the bourgeoisie itself had fallen on the other side of the conflict in the eyes of the Jacobins. However, as time goes by, the subjectivized romantic ego becomes the final metaphysical authority. Romanticism is philosophically revolutionary because it destroys the primacy of reality and replaces it with the primacy of the unlimited emotional possibilities of that ego, also symbolized by the people. Schmitt criticizes sharply this aestheticizing sentimentalism, held by the bourgeoisie. The nineteenth-century romanticism lacks a politicized approach because it dissolves the idea of constituent power into mystical indecision. Marxism will recover the political possibilities of this metaphysical vision.
The revolutionary political possibilities of the theological–political interpretation of Schmitt’s idea of constituent power have been taken to the extreme by Negri in a paradigmatic way. Indeed, Negri, in a magnificent pursuit of Schmittian methodology, has explored Spinozian ideas politically.[82] The same Negri said: “it was Schmitt who refers us to Spinoza.”[83]
Negri’s main thesis is that constituent power resists constitutionalization. For the Italian philosopher, constituent power is a temporary process, a theoretical solution to the challenges of contingency. His idea conducts to an absorption of the constituted reality by an absolute and limitless constituent power that amounts to institutional instability. Negri does not hesitate to denounce the mediations and deviations with which liberal or representative democracy subjects the citizen. Spinoza’s political thought, in his opinion, compresses the production–constitution relation into a unitary nexus. One cannot speak of democracy outside this connection. Democracy is the politics of the multitude, the Spinozian concept, organized in production. Constitution and production are the elements of a fabric from which to construct the experience “of the masses” and the political future, under the form of radical equality imposed by atheism. Power and potency are antagonistic. Power and multitude come to nucleate the model of political society that Negri proposes to us by the hand of Spinoza. In them lies the power to change what is. The teleology of the common lives from its own exposure to historical becoming. It is cooperation that produces and unites the subjectivity of each one in the multitude. Only through cooperation does the multitude become creative and self-governing.
As Koekkoek points out, Negri disregards the Schmittian idea of radical democracy as a democratic dictatorship, but he found in Schmitt an uncompromising articulation of the disconnection of radical democracy from liberal parliamentarianism. He agrees with Schmitt’s interpretation of democracy as a theory of absolute government, as well as his Spinozist–Sieyesian account of constituent power as an all-powerful principle that resists being constitutionalized.[84]
Another contemporary reading of Schmitt that, while seeking to move away from his approaches, leads to revolutionary politics is that of Agamben. He argues that Schmitt’s theory of sovereignty attempts to neutralize the revolutionary implications of the idea of pure violence, which he takes from Benjamin. Indeed, he praises the expression “permanent state of exception,” from Benjamin’s well-known eighth thesis on the philosophy of history, as the ideal of revolutionary politics that manages to transmute the fictitious state of exception, that is generated by the Schmittian idea of exception to the law into a real state of exception, in which the exception has no relation to the law, indeed, in which the exception consists in continually deposing the law. In his opinion, this idea of “inclusive exclusion,” of anomie is the “limit concept of the doctrine of law and the State.”[85] It is to some extent perplexing that Agamben’s reading of the Dictatorship has not visualized the very possibility that he envisages, attributing it only to Benjamin and not to Schmitt himself in his radicalized version of political modernity as a permanent revolution.
4 The Political Theology of Revolution in Political Theology II: The Path to Gnosticism
Underneath the criticisms of the radical version of democracy that Schmitt ironically carries out in Dictatorship and tries to avoid in his Constitutional Theory – and of the aestheticizing revolutionary forms of nationalism and historicism – there is a perceived need in Schmitt to overcome the rigid mechanistic and abstract rationalistic Weltanschauung of Descartes and Hobbes. In fact, at the end of its production, in Political Theology II (1970), Schmitt takes up again Cartesian dualism and its possible resolution in a different way, in particular, as it relates to Gnosticism. In this case, he finds in Gnosticism the new metaphysics underpinning revolutionary politics. In fact, he had already instigated this idea in Political Romanticism:
The root of romantic sublimity is the inability to decide, the ‘higher third’ factor they are always talking about, which is not a higher factor but a different third factor: in other words, it is always a way out of the either-or. Because they leave the decision open – because they construe the occasio ‘antithetically,’ so that it can be the elastic point for the leap to the ‘higher third’ factor – there has been talk of their ‘dualism,’ and reminders of gnostic and Neoplatonic theories have been found, where what was at stake was only the lack of an object, that is characteristic of an occasionalism.[86]
Schmitt takes up the argument on Gnostic dualism years later in Political Theology II, discussing Peterson “liquidation of the political theology of the Reich” in Monotheism as a Political Problem. Peterson suggests that the definition of God as a Trinity does not allow for any monotheistic theological–political transfer. Schmitt then tries to show how a Gnostic interpretation of the Trinitarian dogma allows for a theological–political transposition that interprets the political in a revolutionary way insofar as it places dualism, conflict, enmity, and therefore exception, at the heart of political progressivism. Innovation, that is irruption of the exception, thus functions as the “higher third.”
Peterson used Gregory of Nazianzus’ formulation of the Trinitarian dogma as a key part of his attack on the political theology of the sovereign. Schmitt’s response to Peterson’s objection aimed to show that a political theology that includes the Trinitarian dogma among its dogmas is also possible.[87] Contrary to what might appear at first sight, Schmitt claims that precisely the formulation of this dogma made it clear that it is impossible to separate the theological and political spheres, which would only be possible from an abstract reading of the dogma of the Trinity. Theology and politics cannot be separated because the second person of the Trinity has two natures, divine and human, in one effective unit. Mary gave birth to a divine creature in a historic time and on a particular day. Trinitarian monarchy is a return to the unity of that which comes from itself – that is a return to unity from dualism.
In the end, Schmitt forces the interpretation of Gregory of Nazianzus’ thesis to save his own concept of the political.[88] He translates Nazianzus’ main definition of the Trinity, “to Hen stasiatzon pros heauton,” as “The One is always in uproar against itself.”[89]
Schmitt undoubtedly had his own criteria of the political in mind, that is the friend–enemy distinction. This shows that not only is political theology possible from the dogma of the Trinity but also that precisely this analogy contains the criteria for what is specifically political: the stasis, the exception. To explain the idea of stasis, which is at the core of the definition, Schmitt cited a passage from Plato’s Sophist, where he argues, on the one hand, the impossibility of life where there is calm and, on the other hand, the necessity of unity where there is life.[90] The apparent paradox of movement-unity dialectics is implicit in the term stasis, which means not only Ruhe, rest, status, quiet, place, but also the opposite, Unruhe, movement, uproar, kinesis, politische Unruhe, political unrest, civil war, enmity in unity, politics. A “politico-theological stasiology”[91] appears at the heart of Trinitarian life, in which the problem of the enemy does not hide. The unity of God appears damaged by a certain division.
At this point, political theology can take three paths to explain the stasis in divine unity. One path is Christian and monotheistic, which finds one of its representatives in Augustine, whose ideas Schmitt describes in Political Theology II.[92] The theory of the Trinity does not completely dissolve the identity of god the creator and god the redeemer. They are not identical, but they are still one. Dual natures, God and man, are turned into unity through the action of the third person.[93] Schmitt’s thesis sees in the divine pluripersonality the condition of possibility for plurality and fighting in a political world.[94]
The second path is a dualistic or Gnostic one, the dualism against which Schmitt has fought. From this point of view, god the creator and god the redeemer have always been enemies. This idea, according to Schmitt, is common both to the properly Gnostic movement and to revolutionary politics. The main structural power within Gnostic dualism, that is the problem of the god of creation and the god of salvation, dominates every religion of salvation and redemption. It also inescapably exists in every world in need of change and renewal, and it is both immanent and ineradicable.[95] This enmity is addressed in both Goethe’s old aphorism, “nemo contra deum nisi deus ipse,”[96] which in itself does not contain a theological reference since Goethe used it in a political sense to refer to Napoleon’s power[97] and in Lenz’s fragment, “Catherine of Siena,”[98] which Schmitt connects with the gnostic interpretation of Gregory of Nazianzus’ ideas about Trinity. When the relationship between God the Father and God the Son is interpreted in a dualistic way, as happens in some of the cited texts – that is as a relationship of insurrection or revolution – one enters into sociology of juristic concepts that highlight the problem of the exception at the heart of the theological question.
There is a third, pluralistic path that Schmitt does not regard as political theology, and rather sees it as “politheology.”[99] Blumenberg implemented the clearest form of this approach, especially in his text Arbeit am Mythos.[100] Schmitt argued that there is a difference between writing nemo contra Deum nisi Deus ipse and nemo contra deum nisi deus ipse. Goethe writes god in lowercase. It indicates a struggle between gods, rather than a struggle within one God. A god can only balance its power in a struggle with other gods. This statement belongs to a polytheistic and, therefore, mythological context, rather than to a theological one in the strict sense. It involves the complete rejection of theology and acceptance of paganism. But paganism is also revolutionary.
Blumenberg, however, in Schmitt’s view, maintains a polytheistic interpretation. His description of the new world as permeated with a volt of constant change (erneuerungsbedürftigen), with a constitutive need for progress, change, and novelty, necessarily maintains a divine dialectic. Namely, such a world – despite believing that theology has been substituted by science – retains the structural analogy in which god the creator and god the redeemer are enemies because the conservative force of the created order and the liberating one, that is the executor of the new world, can only be enemies. Schmitt describes this theological–political possibility as follows:
Revolution in contrast to reformation, reform, revision, and evolution, is a hostile struggle. Friendship is almost impossible between the lord of a world in need of change, that is, a misconceived world – a lord who is guilty of this need for change, because he does not support but rather opposes it – and the liberator, the creator of a transformed new world. They are so to speak, by definition, enemies. En temps de revolution tout ce qui est ancient est ennemi [During a revolution everything belonging to the old regime was considered inimical] (Mignet).[101]
As Schmitt also asserts in Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, Marxist historical philosophy and sociology is philosophically and metaphysically fascinating because Marx retains the concept of dialectical development of human history and observes this development as a concrete, unique antithetical process, producing itself through an immanent, organic power.[102] The exception is immanent to the process, and it is continuously produced by the metaphysically relevant antagonism between the bourgeois and the proletary. The Communist Manifesto was new and fascinating because of its systematic concentration of class struggle in the high dialectic tension between the bourgeoisie and proletariat. As Schmitt asserts, this simplification powerfully increased the intensity of the argument. Because the development process is dialectical, and therefore logical, even if it remains economic at the base, a simple antithesis must emerge in the last critical, absolutely decisive turning point of world history. Everything must be forced to the extreme so that, out of dialectical necessity, it can be overturned.[103]
Revolutionary total de-theologization and total depoliticization also, paradoxically, absolutely encounter the enemy. Once on earth, the statement “nemo contra Deum nisi Deus ipse” transforms into, “nemo contra hominen nisi homo ipse,” no one is against man except man himself.[104] Revolutionary politics follows this gnostic or polytheistic theological structure in the last writings of Schmitt.
5 Conclusion: Schmitt’s Political Theological Foundation of Revolution
In the beginning, we wondered: Is there a political theology of revolution in Carl Schmitt or is his political theology only and exclusively autocratic? We are now in a position to give a nuanced answer to this question. Schmitt does not outline a single political theology of revolution, but several possibilities.
From Schmitt’s point of view, the doctrine of constituent power is a revolutionary conceptual engine par excellence. In this article, we have retrieved the juridical genealogy of this doctrine as Schmitt described it in Dictatorship and Constitutional Theory. Although Schmitt’s genealogy of the idea of constituent power is eminently juridical: plenitudo potestatis papalis, arcana, persona ficta, pouvoirs intermediaires, volonté general, and finally pouvoir constituant; he himself admits that a revolutionary constituent power would not exist without a certain transfusion of theological–metaphysical concepts into juridical ideas. This is particularly the case of Spinozian metaphysical expressionism and the concept of law present in Malebranche’s theodicy, and finally the case of Gnostic dualism or pagan polytheism.
These theological paths contributed to the generation of a political theology of revolution that took political consequences in the French and Soviet Revolutions. Concerning the exception, the revolutionary democratic doctrine understood as a sovereign dictatorship significantly innovates in political theory in that it operates a change in the position of the exception, which goes from coming from “outside” the political order to being integrated into it as an element of stasis, that is to say, of destabilization. The exception is constituted as the keystone of political normality itself and not only does not break with legal continuity but acts within it. Hence, all modern politics, under the mask of legality, become permanently revolutionary.
Although Carl Schmitt’s position on constituent power is not revolutionary, given that his Constitutional Theory incorporates material limits to the action of constituent power, his use of the political theology of revolution in Political Theology II brings him closer to a revolutionary approach that keeps the friend–enemy dialectic alive in political life than to Hobbesian monarchical absolutism. Indeed, despite his criticism of radical democracy, there is an interest in – and to a certain extent an admiration for – the theory and practice of that political form, to the extent that it preserves the political element in an age of abstract normativism.
-
Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.
References
Agamben, Giorgio. State of Exception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.10.2307/j.ctv1134d6w.16Search in Google Scholar
Agamben, Giorgio. The Kingdom and the Glory: For a Theological Genealogy of Economy and Government. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011.Search in Google Scholar
Arato, Andrew. “Carl Schmitt and the Revival of the Doctrine of the Constituent Power in the United States.” Cardozo Law Review 21 (2000), 1739–48.Search in Google Scholar
Arato, Andrew. “Forms of Constitution Making and Theories of Democracy.” Cardozo Law Review 17 (1995), 191–213.Search in Google Scholar
Arato, Andrew. “Good-Bye to Dictatorships?” Social Research 67 (2000), 925–55.Search in Google Scholar
Beneyto, José M. Politische Theologie als Politische Theorie: Eine Untersuchung zur Rechts und Staatstheorie Carl Schmitts und ihrer Wirkungsgeschichte in Spanien. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1983.10.3790/978-3-428-45342-9Search in Google Scholar
Blumenberg, Hans. Arbeit am Mythos. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1979.Search in Google Scholar
Breuer, Stefan. “Nationalstaat und pouvoir constituant bei Sieyès und Carl Schmitt.” Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 70:4 (1984), 495–517.Search in Google Scholar
Castrucci, Emanuele. On the Idea of Potency. Juridical and Theological Roots of the Western Cultural Tradition. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2016.10.1515/9781474411868Search in Google Scholar
Clapmarius, Arnoldus. De arcanis rerumpublicarum libri Sex. Editionen zur Frühen Neuzeit 4, 1–2. Stuttgart: frommann-holzboog Verlag e. K, 2013.Search in Google Scholar
Clapmarius, Arnoldus. Conclusiones de Jure Publico. Lodewijk: Elsevier, 1644.Search in Google Scholar
Colon-Rios, Joel I. Weak Constitutionalism. Democratic Legitimacy and the Question of Constituent Power. Abingdon: Routledge, 2012.10.4324/9780203120132Search in Google Scholar
Colon-Rios, Joel I. “Rousseau, Theorist of Constituent Power.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 36:4 (2016), 885–908.10.1093/ojls/gqw012Search in Google Scholar
Collison, Luke. “From the Commissary Dictator to the Katechon: Continuity in Carl Schmitt’s Theory of the Intermediate Authority.” Political Theology (2021). 10.1080/1462317X.2021.1970090.Search in Google Scholar
Conrad, Dieter. “Limitation of Amendment Procedures and the Constituent Power.” In Zwischen den Traditionen. Probleme des Verfassungsrechts und der Rechtskultur in Indien und Pakistan, edited by Dieter Conrad, 47–85. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Cristi, Renato. “Carl Schmitt on Sovereigny and Constituent Power.” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 189 (1997), 189–201.10.1017/S0841820900000308Search in Google Scholar
Ehmke, Horst. Grenzen der Verfassungsänderung. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1953.Search in Google Scholar
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang. Dichtung und Wahrheit. Berlin: Deutsche Buch Gesellschaft, 1967.Search in Google Scholar
Herrero, Montserrat. The Political Discourse of Carl Schmitt. A Mystic of Order. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2015.Search in Google Scholar
Herrero, Montserrat. “Genealogical Practices. Three Ways to Consider the Presence of History in Philosophy.” Giornale di Metafisica 2 (2016), 575–97.Search in Google Scholar
Herrero, Montserrat. “Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology: The Magic of a Phrase,” In Political Theology in Medieval and Early Modern Europe: Discourses, Rites and Representations, edited by Herrero, M., Aurell, J., Miceli, A., 23–43, Turnhout: Brepols, 2017.10.1484/M.MEMPT-EB.5.111244Search in Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. De Homine. Paris: Blanchard, 1974.Search in Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. The Elements of Law Natural and Politic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.Search in Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. De Cive. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 2002.Search in Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Search in Google Scholar
Jaume, Lucien. “La théorie de la ‘personne fictive’ dans le Léviathan de Hobbes.” Revue Française de Science Politique 33/6 (1983), 1009–35.10.3406/rfsp.1983.394103Search in Google Scholar
Kalyvas, Andreas. “Carl Schmitt and the Three Moments of Democracy.” Cardozo Law Review 21 (2000), 1525–66.Search in Google Scholar
Kalyvas, Andreas. Democracy and the Politics of the Extraordinary. Max Weber, Carl Schmitt, and Hannah Arendt. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.10.1017/CBO9780511755842Search in Google Scholar
Kelly, Duncan. “Carl Schmitt’s Political Theory of Dictatorship.” In The Oxford Handbook of Carl Schmitt, edited by Jens Meierhenrich and Oliver Simons, 217–44. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.Search in Google Scholar
Klein, Claude, Théorie et Pratique du Pouvoir Constituant. Paris: PUF, 1996.Search in Google Scholar
Koekkoek, Rene. “Carl Schmitt and the Challenge of Spinoza’s Pantheism between the World Wars.” Modern Intellectual History 11 (2014), 333–57.10.1017/S1479244314000043Search in Google Scholar
Kraft-Fuchs, Margit. “Prinzipielle Bemerkungen zu Carl Schmitts Verfassungslehre.” Zeitschrift für Öffentliches Recht 9 (1930), 511–41.Search in Google Scholar
Languet, Hubert. Arcana Seculi Decimi Sexti: Epistolae Secretae ad Principem Suum Augustum, Sax. Ducem. Halle: J. P. von Ludewig, 1699.Search in Google Scholar
Lenz, Jakob Michael Reinhold. Werke und Schriften II. Stuttgart: Goverts, 1966.Search in Google Scholar
Lukac de Stier, María L. “Potentia Dei: De Tomás de Aquino a Hobbes.” Intus-Legere Filosofía 7 (2013), 43–57.10.15691/0718-5448Vol7Iss1a153Search in Google Scholar
Magalhaes, Pedro T. The Legitimacy of Modern Democracy. A Study on the Political Thought of Max Weber, Carl Schmitt and Hans Kelsen. New York: Routledge, 2020.10.4324/9781315157566Search in Google Scholar
McCormick, John P. “The Dilemmas of Dictatorship: Carl Schmitt and Constitutional Emergency Powers.” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 163 (1997), 163–87.10.1017/S0841820900000291Search in Google Scholar
McCormick, John P. Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism: Against Politics as Technology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
McLoughlin, Daniel. “The Fiction of Sovereignty and the Real State of Exception: Giorgio Agamben’s Critique of Carl Schmitt.” Law, Culture and Humanities 12 (2016), 509–28.10.1177/1743872112469863Search in Google Scholar
Meinecke, Friedich. Reason of State. Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison D'état and Its Place in Modern History. London: Routledge, 1997.Search in Google Scholar
Migne, Jacques, Paul. Patrologiae Cursus Completus. Parisiis: J. P. Migne, 1844.Search in Google Scholar
Mommsen, Momme. “Zur Frage der Herkunft des Spruches ‘Nemo contra deum nisi deus ipse.’” Goethe-Jahrbuch: Vierteljahresschrift der Goethe Gesellschaft 13 (1951), 86–104.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio. Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio. Spinoza for Our Time. Politics and Postmodernity. Columbia: Columbia University Press, 2013.10.7312/negr16046Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio. Le Pouvoir Constituant: Essai Sur les Alternatives de la Modernité. 1992. Paris. Presses Universitaires de France, 1997.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio. Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio and Hardt. Empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio and Hardt. Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire. New York: Penguin Publishing Group, 2004.Search in Google Scholar
Negri, Antonio and Hardt. Commonwealth. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009.10.2307/j.ctvjsf48hSearch in Google Scholar
Oakley, Francis. “The Absolute and Ordained Power of God and King in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Century Theology.” Journal of the History of Ideas 59/3 (1998), 437–61.10.1353/jhi.1998.0027Search in Google Scholar
Oakley, Francis. “The Absolute and Ordained Power of God and King in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries: Philosophy, Science, Politics and Law.” Journal of the History of Ideas 59/4 (1998), 669–90.10.1353/jhi.1998.0041Search in Google Scholar
Oakley, Francis. “The Papal and Imperial Concept of plenitudo potestatis: The influence of Pope Inocent III on Emperor Frederick II.” In Pope Inocent III and his World, edited by John C. Moore, 305–3014. Aldershot: Ashgate, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Ojakangas, Mika. “Potentia absoluta et potentia ordinata Dei: on the theological origins of Carl Schmitt’s Theory of Constitution.” Cont Philos Rev 45 (2012), 505–17.10.1007/s11007-012-9233-xSearch in Google Scholar
Ors, Álvaro d’. De la guerra y de la paz. Madrid: Rialp, 1954.Search in Google Scholar
Plato, Theaetetus and Sophist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.Search in Google Scholar
Ratzinger, Joseph. Shauen auf den Durchbohrten. Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1984.Search in Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean J. The Social Contract and the First and Second Discourses. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002.Search in Google Scholar
Rubinelli, Lucia. Constituent Power: a History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020.10.1017/9781108757119Search in Google Scholar
Salzborn, Samuel. “The Will of the People? Carl Schmitt and Jean-Jacques Rousseau on a Key Question in Democratic Theory.” Democratic Theory Summer 4:1 (2017), 11–34.10.3167/dt.2017.040102Search in Google Scholar
Sheuerman, William E. Carl Schmitt: The End of Law. Lanham, Md: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
Sheuerman, William E. Between the Norm and the Exception. The Frankfurt School and the Rule of Law. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Constitutional Theory. NC: Duke University Press, 2007.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. “Clausewitz als Politischer Denker: Bemerkungen und Hinweise.” Der Staat 6 (1967), 478–502.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Political Romanticism. MA: MIT Press, 1986.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. “Der Staat als Mechanismus bei Hobbes und Descartes.” Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 30 (1936), 622–32.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure of a Political Symbol. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1996.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. “Dialogue on Power and Access to the Holder of Power.” In Dialogues on Power and Space, edited by Andreas Kalyvas and Federico Finchelstein, 23–51. Cambridge: Polity, 2015.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Dictatorship: From the Origin of the Modern Concept of Sovereignty to Proletarian Class Struggle. Cambridge: Polity, 2014.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.10.7208/chicago/9780226738901.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology II: The Myth of the Closure of Any Political Theology. New York: Polity Press, 2014.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, The Crises of Parliamentary Democracy. Cambridge. Mass: MIT Press, 2000.Search in Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. “Die politische Theorie des Mythus,” In Schmitt, Positionen und Begriffe im Kampf mit Weimar-Genf-Versailles, 1923–39, 9–18. Hamburg: Hanseatische Verlagsanstalt, 1940.Search in Google Scholar
Schupmann, Benjamin. Carl Schmitt’s State and Constitutional Theory. A Critical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.10.1093/oso/9780198791614.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Sieyès, Abbé. Qu’est-ce que le Tiers Etat? Paris: Flammarion, 2018.Search in Google Scholar
Vatter, Miguel. “Strauss and Schmitt as Readers of Hobbes and Spinoza: On the Relation between Political Theology and Liberalism.” The New Centennial Review 4 (2004), 161–214.10.1353/ncr.2005.0025Search in Google Scholar
Vinx, Lars. “Are There Inherent Limits to Constitutional Amendment? An Analysis of Carl Schmitt’s Argument.” In Constituent Power: Law, Popular Rule and Politics, edited by Matilda Arvidsson, Leila Brändström, and Panun Minkinnen, 61–76. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2020.10.1515/9781474454995-005Search in Google Scholar
Walther, Manfred. “Carl Schmitt contra Baruch Spinoza oder Vom Ende der politischen Theologie.” In: Spinoza in der europäischen Geistesgeschichte, edited by H. Delf, J. H. Schoeps, and M. Walther (Hrsg.), 422–41. Berlin: Edition Hentrich, 1994.Search in Google Scholar
© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.