Skip to content
BY 4.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter Open Access June 6, 2023

The Metaphysical Contention of Political Theology

  • Luís Carneiro EMAIL logo
From the journal Open Theology

Abstract

The question of the exact role of theology in Schmitt’s political theology remains undecided. Several authors have raised this question and distinct answers have been given. In order to reach an accurate representation of the political–theological dimension in Schmitt’s work, I will attempt an interpretation which takes into account not only Schmitt’s more widely known theses, but also the perceived esoteric and unsaid aspects of his work. Against Heinrich Meier’s prominent thesis, in his The Lesson of Carl Schmitt, of the strict theological nature of political theology, my thesis is that Schmitt gives precedence to the political over theology and that political theology is a theology and metaphysics of the political. Starting from Peterson’s theological objections, centered on Trinitarian dogma and eschatology, I will reconstruct the trail of political theology throughout Schmitt’s work in view of its epitome in the notion of a Trinitarian stasiology and in the figure of the katechon. It is the connection between these two themes which defines Schmitt’s positive and polemical political theology, which can be designated as a katechontic and metastatic political theology. The katechon itself will be defined as the metapolitical and transcendental condition of possibility of the political. The Nomos of the Earth will also be a necessary reference point for the correct understanding of the connection between theology and politics, given the theme of “detheologization,” as well as Schmitt’s lifelong engagement with the problem of the state in the work of Thomas Hobbes.

Les dieux s’en vont,

les théologiens restent

26.1.71 C.S.

1 Introduction

What is theological in Schmitt’s conception of political theology? What role does theology play in a specifically political theology. Is political theology a theology in any meaningful sense of the term and, if so, in what way?

These questions have been raised about Schmitt’s political theology and different types of answers have been given.[1] I will attempt here to deal with the presuppositions of this problem in Schmitt’s work and to establish the coordinates for what I consider to be a more accurate representation of its political–theological core, its purpose, and strategic stakes. In the context of this special issue, it is opportune to return to the question of the meaning of political theology in the totality of Schmitt’s work.

Heinrich Meier’s thesis on the eminently theological basis of Schmitt’s political theology will serve as a counterpoint for this article. Meier’s book The Lesson of Carl Schmitt had the undisputable merit of having inaugurated a more fundamental type of questioning, one which approaches Schmitt’s oeuvre in its globality, taking into account Schmitt’s public and private writings, his explicit and implicit positionings, and the “esoteric” and unsaid dimensions of his work. The same integral and synthesizing approach to Schmitt’s work will be used here, but with different conclusions.

Meier’s thesis portrays Schmitt as a thinker whose entire theoretical position and existential attitude are based on faith in revelation and on the “commandment of obedience” to the sovereign authority of God in accordance with such faith, manifested in an inexorable call to historical action. This implies that Schmitt’s concept of the political is subordinated to theology and grounded in a theological foundation which is not itself inherently political but extra-political. Contrary to this thesis, I hold that what is specifically theological in Schmitt’s political theology is, above all, a theology and a metaphysics of the political. The concept of the political is primary in Schmitt’s thinking and all theological elements in Schmitt’s thinking serve a fundamental purpose of politicization, not of depoliticization. But it needs to be stressed that this is not a mere inversion of Meier’s position, first, because, for Meier, the theological foundation of politics means that politics is ultimately neutralized and obliterated, while in this interpretation the reverse is not true, i.e., theology is not entirely subsumed in politics, and, second, because the way the two domains relate to each other is complex and without a direct causal precedence of one over the other. The fact that theology itself has a politicizing effect in Schmitt’s thinking does not mean that theology is “instrumentalized” by politics, but is due to the basic structural affinity that Schmitt identifies between theology and jurisprudence, expressed by the idea of a “political form” inherent in theology itself. As we will see, this has to be understood, ultimately, in accordance with a type of historical thinking congruent with the eschatological shape and orientation of the Christian aeon in which we live, according to Schmitt. It is only in this mediated way that theology has a proper political form, since in its immediate, but undeclared, political use, by pretending to dictate its own terms to politics, it has the opposite depoliticizing effect.

My point of departure will be the debate between Schmitt and Erik Peterson, in particular, Peterson’s understanding of the problem of a Christian political theology which would constitute the basis for his rejection of Schmitt’s political theology. This debate has been abundantly discussed, but it will be necessary to briefly analyze some of its aspects, given its importance for Schmitt’s articulation of his final political–theological position around the two points of contention of eschatology and Trinitarianism. Peterson’s critique was the first attempt to redirect the debate on the meaning of political theology to the question of its theological presuppositions and to argue against the possibility of political theology on the basis of eschatology and Trinitarianism. Building upon this basis, this will allow us to perceive how Schmitt, led by Peterson’s objections, ultimately reveals his own metaphysical conception of political theology, which, I claim, can be understood as a synthetic recapitulation of his whole work and of its fundamental purpose. In this sense, the two fundamental axes of this political theology are the katechon and Trinitarian stasiology.

In the search for the integral and positive meaning of political theology in Schmitt, I reject the methodology, exemplified by Montserrat Herrero, which approaches Schmitt’s oeuvre in a fragmentary manner and postulates the existence of different “political theologies” without any synthetic overall meaning, with the exception of political theology understood as a descriptive scientific rubric under the heading of a “sociology of juristic concepts.”[2] In this interpretation, it is affirmed that there is the general scientific account and different tentative political theologies, each one of them based on a specific political–theological analogy, including a “political theology of the sovereign,” a “political theology of state’s representation,” a “political theology of revolution,”[3] and the “political theology of the katechon.” This scheme is helpful to establish a contrast with my own reading of Schmitt, since here I argue, precisely, how all of these supposed different political theologies are in fact different aspects of the same fundamental position. I claim that it is a misperception and a categorical mistake to understand these different thematizations as unconnected analogies or genealogical projects, when, in fact, their unity can be demonstrated precisely by showing how Schmitt’s positive political theology is a theology of the political. Ultimately, it is simply disingenuous to maintain that there is no specific positive scope or polemical purpose in Schmitt’s political theology and that political theology is just a purely scientific project. This is not to deny that there is a scientific and descriptive import in political theology, understood as a theological genealogy of modern political concepts, but it is unreasonable to assert that this is its only meaning.

Böckenförde’s already classical scheme of the three different types of political theology, “juridical,” “institutional,” and “appellative,” where only the first could be properly applied to Schmitt’s project, again in the sense of a descriptive sociology of concepts, which Herrero follows, is also insufficient to describe what exactly Schmitt’s positive and polemical type of political theology is.[4] I claim that this specific argumentation was typical of an initially apologetic phase of Schmittian scholarship which is no longer feasible. Meier, who never once in his book refers to Böckenförde or to his typology, used a specific Straussian idea of an esoteric “art of writing” in order to detect in Schmitt a theological foundation for his thinking. Even though I also consider Schmitt’s positive political theology to be an esoteric and unsaid position, this can be explained not by any sort of obfuscating strategy on the part of Schmitt, but by appeal to the notion of “metapolitics,” where the prefix “meta-” is rigorously understood in all its implications, which will allow us to evidence the performative nature of Schmitt’s theoretical positions and concepts. In order to do so, I will also briefly engage with the work of Matthias Lievens, who applied this concept to Schmitt’s body of work in a productive manner. The understanding of Schmitt’s project as a “metapolitical struggle,” a struggle for politicization itself, against all forms of depoliticization, is key to understanding his own engaged and polemical type of political theology.

In Section 3, I will show how political plurality depends on the conceptual unity of the “political entity,” which is itself defined by the concept of the political, and how the state, as the political agency of the jus publicum Europaeum, became the fundamental instance of politicization in modern jurisprudence and, thus, the primary form of the historical dispensation of the political in modernity, while at the same time being a force of detheologization. The theme of detheologization, developed in The Nomos of the Earth, renders eminently problematic the thesis of the theological foundation of Schmitt’s thinking. In Section 4, I argue how “metapolitics” represents the most appropriate methodological approach to and explanation of Schmitt’s esotericism. Not only this, but also Schmitt’s metapolitical struggle, defined as the struggle between the political and the unpolitical, or as the struggle for politicization, constitutes the very decisive trait of his political theology in its polemical sense. This metapolitical struggle is also defined, in figurative terms, as the struggle between the katechon and the Antichrist, wherein the katechon, by prolonging Schmitt’s early idea of the “political form” in a different register, comes to stand for the very transcendental condition of possibility of the political. Next, since Hobbes’s name will recur as a major landmark in Schmitt’s final answer – Political Theology II ends with reference to Hobbes – I will also analyze the way in which the problem of political theology was posed in Schmitt’s 1938 Leviathan book, as well as in subsequent references to Hobbes, where we can observe a radical shift in Schmitt’s conception of the problematic of the Hobbesian state. This shift is observable in the 1963 Hinweise to the Concept of the Political, as well as in the overlooked, but crucial, 1965 essay Die Vollendete Reformation. Without taking this into account, Schmitt’s final political–theological position is incomprehensible. This analysis will allow us to understand how the themes of the state and of the katechon, as the containment of civil war and disorder, relate to the theological paradigm of stasis, which will be explored in Section 6. The relation and inner coherence of the themes of the katechon and stasis constitutes the main contribution of this article. It is the connection between the katechon and Trinitarian stasiology, which defines Schmitt’s positive political theology, which is, at the same time, katechontic and stasiological, or, more properly, metastatic. It is the nexus between the notions of political form, the katechon, and stasis, which defines Schmitt’s political–theological synthesis, as a theology of the political, implicitly presented in Political Theology II as the summation and epitome of his entire work. Since the presentation of this nexus requires a synoptic view of some of Schmitt’s main themes developed throughout his work, my argumentation will be relatively lengthy and as much as possible exhaustive.

2 Monotheism, Trinitarianism, Eschatology

One way to understand Peterson’s critique is that he considers Schmitt’s political theology as a normative enterprise, according to which, in a secularized context, an analogy could be established between divine or theological monarchy and human or political monarchy, an analogy that would allow the legitimation of political sovereignty, founded in a purely structural way and sharing the same metaphysical structure of divine sovereignty. This critique already contained in nuce what would become the oft-repeated imputation that Schmitt’s secularization theorem stands for a covert way of grounding modern politics in theology, whether on the basis of its historical and genealogical filiation in theology or on the basis of structural analogies between theological concepts and political concepts. This was the implicit meaning of Peterson’s genealogical reference, in Monotheism as a Political Problem, to Arianism, which served as a critical device for a problem contemporary to Peterson, namely that of the instrumentalization of religion by the state or the use of religion for the purposes of legitimizing political power.[5] This reduction of the theological realm to the political realm is what underlies the Petersonian understanding of the notion of “political theology,” which he criticizes in the essay.

For Peterson, the representative of Arian political theology was the imperial advisor Eusebius of Caesarea. Unlike his teacher Origen, who understood the pax augusta as a providential means for the spreading of the Gospel, Eusebius reinterpreted it as the realization of a unity which was analogous to the monotheistic divinity of the Christian God. This unification was the result of the abolition of national plurality, which implied the constant threat of war and sedition and, therefore, the Roman Empire had already realized the eschatological peace promised by the prophets.[6] Where a pluralistic world implies a polytheistic metaphysics, with the end of the disparate rule of the nations, polytheism loses its political condition of possibility. In this sense, the Roman Empire in its monarchical form was already structurally Christian and it was with Constantine that its monotheistic potential came to be fully realized.[7] Moreover, Christianity was more metaphysically appropriate as an imperial religion, since it was formally consistent with unitary monotheism.[8] According to Peterson, in his subordination of theology to politics, Eusebius had made a “political choice” for the Roman Empire. Eusebius’ theology would thus be a political theology, structurally similar to pagan political theology, since it conceives of monotheism as a result of a political–metaphysical complex, whereby political realities make possible, through a metaphysical analogy, theological realities. From this point of view, Christian eschatology yields to historical realization and theology is politicized.

In Peterson’s understanding, the primary consequence of the political–theological structure of Arian monotheism is the subordination of the Church to the Empire and, subsequently, the subordination, absorption, or instrumentalization of theology by political power. This structure also grounds the possibility of political totalitarianism, primarily because it has as its central effect the loss of the “eschatological proviso” of the Church, by equating the goals and domains of religion and politics.

For Peterson, this monotheistic political theology would come to an end due to orthodox Trinitarian doctrine, which robbed the idea of divine Monarchy of its political–theological character. This was expressed in a particularly acute way by Gregory of Nazianzus, who “laid to rest monotheism as a political problem” and theologically dissolved the “linkage of the Christian proclamation to the Roman Empire.” As Peterson summarizes it, for Saint Gregory, “there were three options about God: anarchy, polyarchy, and monarchy. The first two assumptions unleashed disorder and revolt in God, and ultimately dissolution. Christians, on the other hand, confessed the Monarchy of God. To be sure, not the Monarchy of a single person of the godhead, for this bore the seed of schism within itself, but the Monarchy of the triune God.” Moreover, since the Trinitarian conception of unity possesses no analogy with the created order, for Peterson, all attempts at founding a political order on the basis of the Trinitarian dogma would be ipso facto impossible. With Trinitarian theology, the derivation of metaphysical monotheism from the imperial monarchy is abolished and the metaphysical sanction of imperial monarchy by a monotheistic theology is abolished as well.

Besides Saint Gregory’s condemnation of purely monotheistic monarchy in the name of the Trinity, Peterson saw another condemnation of Christian political theology in Augustine’s critique of the Augustan peace, which had not really put to end wars and civil wars, contrary to the assertion of the panegyrists, such as Eusebius, and could not in any way be interpreted as the fulfillment of the eschatological peace prophesied in the Old Testament. This peace could only be realized in the kingdom of heaven at the end of time and as a gift of grace within the Church.

As Schmitt would later summarize it, Peterson’s critique of political theology was articulated according to two axes: Trinitarian theology and eschatology. For Peterson, 1) a correct understanding of the Trinitarian dogma and 2) the recognition of the eschatological dimension of Christianity forbid any political realization of the divine monarchy and invalidate from the outset any political theology.[9] According to Peterson, the dogma of the Trinity and the notion of eschatological peace mark, in the Christian regime, the radical and insurmountable separation of the theological and the political.

As we will see – and this is key to the understanding of Schmitt’s final form of political theology – Schmitt’s answer was strictly coordinated with these two critical axes, even to the point of proposing a distinct interpretation of the Nazianzene’s words and making it a singular point of contention. Yet, for Schmitt, the core of Peterson’s critique was in fact related to eschatology.[10] Schmitt’s own final position will be intimately bound to the problem of eschatology. But, in order to understand the meaning and scope of Schmitt’s final reply to Peterson in Political Theology II, which would reframe the problem of political theology, we need first to define what exactly was at stake in Schmitt’s concept and theory of the political and in what way it relates to political theology. Since the scope of this article is limited to the function of theology in political theology, I will not address Schmitt’s “scientific” critique of Peterson’s essay, which performed the more external role of a methodological refutation of some of Peterson’s contradictions,[11] but, as previously stated, I will focus on the esoteric debate and on the true contention at play therein.[12]

3 Pluralism, the State, and Detheologization

Another less explored facet of Peterson’s critique of Schmitt’s political theology regards the problem of nationalism and pluralism.[13] To some extent, Peterson’s enumeration of the different types of political theology, Jewish, Pagan, and Arian tried to force Schmitt, as a political theologian, to see his own position as a reflection of these three types or to reject political theology altogether, if he was to remain a Christian. The pagan model of national pluralism, in particular, raises the problem of whether Schmitt’s political theory can be considered nationalist and therefore pagan.[14]

Heinrich Meier shows clearly that the fundamental issue for Schmitt is not nationalism. Nationalism would be, according to Meier, a specific occasion of what he calls a historical mission or dispensation of political theology, thought of as the nexus of divine revelation and providence in history.[15] For Meier, Schmitt’s thought would be characterized as responding to a call for historical action, having as its purpose the ordering of human politics to theological ends. Schmitt’s political positions, whose immediate goal would correspond to a strategy of repoliticization, in accordance with his concept of the political, would have as their true purpose and mission the affirmation of divine sovereignty and the reassertion of a moral and theological enmity between political types compatible with this affirmation, even in secular contexts and arrangements, and political (or unpolitical) types structurally incompatible with divine sovereignty.

In my view, Meier’s thesis regarding historical missions as strategies of repoliticization is correct, but not because politics in Schmitt is subordinate to theology, but, on the contrary, the concept of the political is more fundamental than theology. His assertion in the preface to the 1934 second edition of Political Theology that “the political is the total,”[16] which he maintained in later editions of the book, does not have any other meaning. In his reply to Peterson, Schmitt not only argues that Peterson’s attempted theological liquidation of political theology is actually a political act, but also asserts, more fundamentally, that the very dimension of the political is present at the heart of the Trinitarian dogma.

Schmitt would agree with the association between nationalism and polytheism, i.e., that what is at stake in nationalism is a form of political–theological or, more precisely, political–mythological pluralism.[17] Moreover, the worldview of nationalist pluralism could be referred to what Schmitt, in the 1933 edition of the Concept of the Political, calls the “agonal” metaphysical position, according to which political distinctions could be neutralized in a medium of generalized homogeneity and equivalence. But in Schmitt’s own metaphysical view, a polemical–political view that from the 1960s onward explicitly becomes a stasiological view, the friend/enemy distinction constitutes a non-dialectical unity of tension, not reconcilable in a homeostatic unity reducible to sameness, but defined by a split internal to identity, in which the neutralized dialectic of the same/other takes the fundamental and irreducible form of the friend/enemy distinction. For Schmitt, this metaphysical structure, which in Political Theology II is presented as immanent to the dogma of the Trinity, is neither a simple unity, nor a mere dualism, nor a pluralism in itself absolute, but a “stasis of the one against itself.”

According to a widespread reading of Schmitt, his thought would be mainly characterized as pluralism sans phrase, a radical form of agonal thinking which would value political plurality above all else, but a conflictual plurality, erected to the status of norm and irreducible to mere social or liberal pluralism.[18] But this view ignores that Schmitt’s conception of a political pluriversum, of a plurality of equally sovereign nation-states, in the context of his theory of international law, cannot be reduced to a form of geopolitical realism, whether descriptive or normative, which would overlook its strictly conceptual and metaphysical dimension. For Schmitt, the essential of the political pluriversum is located in a metaphysical structure inherent to the concept of the state and state sovereignty, which constituted the central agency of the jus publicum Europaeum, a structure which pertains to the conceptual systematicity of jurisprudence.[19]

As Schmitt writes in the Concept of the Political:

The political entity presupposes the real existence of an enemy and therefore coexistence with another political entity. As long as a state exists, there will thus always be in the world more than just one state. A world state which embraces the entire globe and all of humanity cannot exist. The political world is a pluriverse, not a universe. In this sense every theory of state is pluralistic, even though in a different way from the domestic theory of pluralism.[20]

As it is plain here, Schmitt defines plurality by unity and not unity by plurality. Schmitt does not start from the empirical existence of a plurality of states or political entities in order to define the reality of the state, but, on the contrary, deduces this plurality from the unity of the political entity. Plurality itself is presupposed by the unity of the political entity since this unity is constituted by the friend/enemy distinction, which defines the concept of the political.[21]

Meier either did not pay enough attention or did not understand this aspect of Schmitt’s thought and the real fascination that the conceptual coherence of jurisprudence exerted on Schmitt. As an attempt at refuting a famous passage from Ex Captivitate Salus where Schmitt states “I am a jurist and no theologian,”[22] Meier presents Schmitt’s self-characterization as “a theologian of jurisprudence”[23] in the Glossarium as a simple acknowledgement of his theological grounding and heritage.[24] But Meier neglects the specific way in which Schmitt defines the political–theological analogies between law (Recht) or order or Nomos[25] and God throughout his work, in a manner that law (Recht), order, and Nomos are sacralized as such, whereas natural law is rejected.[26] Schmitt does not reject natural law on the basis of a Kierkegaardian type of fideism, as Meier argues, understood as an irrationalist voluntarism against attempts to rationalize the divine command operative in history – a rationalization that would be akin to legal normativism in its attempt to eradicate the irreducible moments of decision and exception – but on the basis of a sacralization of law (Recht) and order as such, distinct from a natural or substantial law referred to its position by divine will.[27]

In his book, Meier almost entirely ignores The Nomos of the Earth, which is one of Schmitt’s most systematic jurisprudential works – only comparable to Constitutional Theory (also for the most part ignored by Meier).[28] In general, Schmitt’s theses on Nomos, war, and international law could only be ignored by Meier, since they are entirely contrary to his own thesis of the political–theological core of Schmitt’s work, understood as founded on revelation and on the obedience of faith.[29] In fact, the state as the agency of the spatial order of the jus publicum Europaeum could be seen as one specific historical dispensation in the realization of the political. But its specific accomplishment was the detheologization of international law.[30] So how could this mission be political–theological, in the sense that Meier understands it? Meier does not refer to the historical role of the state in establishing a non-discriminatory concept of war, which distinguishes enemies from criminals, but only to Schmitt’s temporary allegiances against depoliticization, such as political Catholicism, nationalism, plebiscitary democracy, and fascism. These examples, even though correct, are tendentious insofar as they associate Schmitt’s metapolitical struggle with specific ideologies and tend to reduce the concept of the political to empirical political engagements, whereas the historical mission of the state as such is an eminently formal example of the struggle against depoliticization and its most fundamental modality as a means of the rationalization of war, of its hedging (Hegung), and containment.

4 Metapolitics and Metastasis

The cryptic, enigmatic, and esoteric dimension of Schmitt’s work, the impression that some of his works give of allusively addressing matters that are not explicitly stated, is due to the tense simultaneity of descriptive and polemical aspects in his political and political–theological theory. At stake in Schmitt’s concept of the political is not only the capacity to describe the political character of actual relations, in the sense of the distinction between friend and enemy, but also, more eminently, the politicizing effect of such description, which is itself generative of the political.[31] The concept of the political is itself political and it is the specific power of the concept to pose the political, not with regard to the content of a given distinction between friends and enemies, but to the possibility of the political as such.

According to Matthias Lievens, this tension between the descriptive and the polemical or political effect of the concept of the political can be characterized as “metapolitical.”[32] Even though this designation is not employed by Schmitt himself and is problematic as a representation of Schmitt’s theoretical self-presentation, I agree that it has explanatory potential and utility, especially to illuminate those aspects of Schmitt’s work which remain esoteric and unsaid. This designation can only be adequate insofar as the prefix meta- implies self-referentiality – the metapolitical is itself political – and does not mean an explicitly formulable meta-level constituted as a distinct – apolitical, non-polemical – domain from that of the base-level descriptive theory.

The conceptual distinction between the political and the metapolitical is particularly useful in leading the analysis of Schmitt’s work away from an unproductive line of questioning which tries to identify who or what exactly was Schmitt’s political enemy qua enemy of the political – whether it was liberalism, communism, anarchy, or even Judaism. Since the politicizing effect of the concept of the political itself does not apply to political relations at the level of content, but at the level of form or possibility, Schmitt’s political theory cannot be situated within the field of empirical political relations – or, simply said, politics – or reduced to a specific ideological position among others. The metapolitical struggle, as Lievens calls it, cannot be reduced to a struggle within the political domain qua politics, such as, for instance, conservatism versus progressivism, but is a struggle for the possibility of the political as such, against all forms of depoliticization.

But this self- or “meta-referential” dimension of his theory means that the positions and concepts which Schmitt develops in his works can be read as applying to the theory itself and to its performative effects. It is precisely because the metalevel of the theory does not constitute a separate domain, distinct from the base-level descriptive texture of his works, that the concepts which are elaborated at this base-level are also reflected on Schmitt’s own theoretical position. In Schmitt, the metapolitical is itself political and does not constitute a separate sphere, and while it remains unsaid, it exhibits itself in its theoretical position.

In the particular case of the Theory of the Partisan, which deals with the post-war paradigm of civil war, analyzed by Lievens, the position of the partisan is reflected on Schmitt’s actual metapolitical engagement, which, according to the hegemonic theoretical coordinates of postwar twentieth century international law, is itself in a position of partisanship.[33] The theoretical and conceptual coordinates of the current “global civil war” not only place every political actor in the position of partisan, it also inevitably place the theory of the political itself in a position of asymmetry, which reflects one of the most decisive empirical characteristics of the partisan. Stasis becomes metastasis and the theoretician of the state finds himself in the position of arguing for the foundations of the concept of the state beyond the state.[34]

The metapolitical struggle between the political and the unpolitical raises the problem beyond mere recognition, since the unpolitical is unwilling to recognize the political, i.e., to recognize the concept of enmity and war as such. The transcendental, metapolitical enmity is not an empirical enmity between friends and enemies, but the enmity between the political and the unpolitical. This struggle between the political and the unpolitical assumes the ultimate form of a metastatic contention, characterized by a transcendental asymmetry.

Contrary to the empirical type of civil war that Schmitt constantly returns to, exemplified by the religious civil wars of the seventeenth century, which were driven by conceptions of just war from both sides, where the enemy was morally disqualified and condemned, with terribly destructive consequences, the asymmetry in question here is between an unpolitical position which does not recognize the other as an enemy nor the concept of enmity and a political position which recognizes the other as enemy and poses enmity as such. The unpolitical is averse to recognition, be it in terms of recognizing or being recognized as a political position, it can only relate to the political in the form of stasis and absolute enmity.

Within the Christian historical aeon and in the horizon of the eschatological time inaugurated by the Christ-event, this metastatic struggle takes the form of the enmity between secular (un)political messianism and the katechon.[35] This does not mean that Schmitt is a strict Christian thinker driven by faith in revelation, but that he considers the Christian historical–eschatological horizon unsurpassable in the shaping of metapolitical relations and positions. Ultimately, (un)political messianism, for Schmitt, is essentially identical with the spirit of technicity and its activist metaphysics. But precisely since it is spirit and metaphysics it is also eminently theological, albeit in the form of an anti- or counter-theology. In the political–theological drama of the Christian aeon, the struggle between the political and the unpolitical is configured as the struggle between the katechon and the Antichrist.[36]

The metastatic struggle between the political and the unpolitical acquires a political–theological guise through a specific ambivalent relation and inversion, whereby it is the unpolitical which manifests itself as an eminently theological position, given that it is unable to recognize the legitimacy of its enemy and reduces the enemy to something whose very existence is unjustified.[37] This inversion is due to the fact that for Schmitt what is fundamentally at stake in Christianity and its historical configuration is not its theology but its political form. Initially, Schmitt defines this political form as a feature of the Roman Catholic Church, but from the 1930s onward this political form will be defined by the concept of the state – depicted by Hobbes as a “mortal God” – consistent with the spatial order of the jus publicum Europaeum. Nonetheless, the state does not coincide with the political form as such, in its absoluteness, but only with one of its historical specifications, albeit the most decisive one and the one with the highest level of historical formality, which expresses what for Schmitt was the fundamental and primary metaphysical neutralization of the theological. The contingency of the state form became patent with the dissolution of the jus publicum Europaeum and the Eurocentric Nomos of the Earth. Schmitt’s absolute political form, understood as the metapolitical and transcendental condition of possibility of the political as such, is not the Catholic Church but the katechon. The political form is, thus, also metastatic in the etymological sense of over and beyond the state.[38]

The Christian political form of the katechon is not, as Meier believes, essentially defined by the dogma of the original sin, politically translated in the attitude of anthropological pessimism which postulates the inevitability of political enmity, but by its eschatological horizon.[39] This relates to the problem of messianism and millennialism. Schmitt’s initial emphasis in the Concept of the Political is on the dangerousness and dynamic character of human beings, politically analogous to the theological dogma of original sin, as a determinant of the inevitability of enmity and war. Later, starting with the Leviathan book, the emphasis will shift to the impossibility of the millennial realization of heaven on Earth, understood as a state of total depoliticization and eradication of all enmity.[40] The preeminent Christian eschatological axiom is that “my kingdom is not of this world” (John 18:36).[41]

Contrary to Peterson’s basic thesis that Schmitt’s theological–political decision is fundamentally anti-eschatological, Schmitt retains the horizon of eschatological openness against its abolition in millennialism. Moreover, in Political Theology II, the struggle and difference between the katechon and (un)political messianism will reach its apotheosis in its stasiological prototype within the Christian theological dogma of the Trinity itself. The preliminary enunciation of this metaphysical contention is theological:

But what is still needed is a word about the criterion for the political and for a political theology; that is, about the distinction between friend and enemy. Peterson in his teaching on the Christian Trinity refers decisively to a passage in Gregory of Nazianzus (Oratio Theologica iii 2) which revolves around this formulation: The One – to Hen – is always in uproar – stasiazon – against itself – pros heauton. Right in the middle of the most precise formulation of this difficult dogma, we find the word stasis in the sense of ‘uproar.’ … With this concept an intriguing contradiction of a dialectical nature emerges. Stasis means in the first place quiescence, tranquility, standpoint, status; its antonym is kinesis, movement. But stasis also means, in the second place, (political) unrest, movement, uproar and civil war. … At the heart of the doctrine of Trinity we encounter a genuine politico-theological stasiology. Thus the problem of enmity and of the enemy cannot be ignored.[42]

Yet this does not mean that the political form is derived from the theological concept, rather that the theological concept is itself the absolutization of the political in its highest level of intensity, reaching into the metaphysical as the crystallization of a metapolitical and metastatic contention.

5 That Jesus is the Christ

Before we further analyze this point, we will have to elucidate the role of Hobbes in Schmitt’s political theology. In 1938, making Helmut Schelsky’s words his own, Schmitt identifies political theology with potestas indirecta:

With the picture of the leviathan, “Hobbes challenges every theory of state fraught by religion, assuming thereby a place among the great political thinkers. … But “the deep meaning of his concept of the leviathan” consists of the concreteness of the “earthly” and “mortal” god who is totally attuned to the political deed of man, who, time and time again, must bring him out of the “chaos” of a “natural” condition. In this way Hobbes led “his historically timely struggle against political theology in all its forms.” The leviathan is the big symbol of this battle. However, according to Schelsky’s conception – and in the precise sense of his conception of theorists of political action – the success of the struggle depends on whether the myth of the leviathan forged by Hobbes constitutes a faithful restoration of the original unity of life, whether the leviathan withstood the test of being the politico-mythical image battling the Judeo-Christian destruction of natural unity, and whether he was equal to the severity and malice of such a battle.[43]

This equation of political theology with potestas indirecta was the expression of a polemical attitude toward the Catholic Church (and Catholic authors like Maritain and Peterson), from which he had lapsed, but simultaneously of a cautious distancing from the concept of political theology, given his precarious political situation.[44] Helmut Schelsky had published an article in 1938, in reply to Schmitt’s 1937 article The State as Mechanism in Hobbes and Descartes, which contained many of the same ideas that would be developed in the 1938 book. In his article, Schelsky strongly criticized “political theology” (but not Schmitt by name) and presented Hobbes as a defender of politics against religious intervention. Schmitt explicitly agreed with him in his book.[45]

But there is another contention at stake in this matter. In 1938, Schmitt’s reading of Hobbes served as a way for him to critically identify political theology with potestas indirecta and to reject every form of political theology in the name of the total state, defined by an “original unity of life” between politics and religion. Later, in 1965, in Die Vollendete Reformation, a crucial but neglected essay, he radically changes his view and sees Hobbes as the major exponent of political theology instead. This change implied a fundamental restructuring of his political–theological project, which he would articulate in 1969. Only with reference to the broader debate on the notion of political theology does this change become intelligible. His position on Hobbes, reworked in 1965, would constitute a decisive element in his final conception of political theology in Political Theology II.

The shift between 1938 and 1965 vis-à-vis Hobbes pivots around the notion of political theology, which, I claim, Schmitt disavowed for some time.[46] I claim, as well, that Schmitt’s equation of political theology with potestas indirecta – against which he, like Hobbes, was resolutely opposed – was in fact his first answer to Peterson, even though the latter’s name was not mentioned. His polemical defense of the “pagan” unity of politics and religion must be read in the same manner, against the “Judeo-Christian” attempts at radically separating the two domains.[47] In this sense, “political theology,” as potestas indirecta, becomes an illegitimately politicized theology, a theology which intervenes in political matters while disavowing its own political position. This would correspond to Schmitt’s critique, in the 1934 preface to Political Theology, of a theological position which pretends to decide on what is political and unpolitical and on its own position as unpolitical. If my claim is correct, in 1938, “political theology” specifically designated this position and it could be read as an inversion and use of Peterson’s argument against himself, where now Peterson’s own position would be the representative par excellence of political theology as potestas indirecta. Later, after Schmitt rehabilitated the notion of political theology, this understanding of the notion would constitute one of its aspects, but no longer the only one. The same criticism was directed at Peterson, but it became an attestation of the inevitability of political theology and no longer a motive for its rejection.

In his previous work, it was not clear whether the Leviathan-state could be identified with the katechon – the upholder of Christian order, political form, and the restrainer of eschatological dissolution. His last word on Hobbes will consist precisely in this idea, grounded in the major axis of his final interpretation, namely that “Jesus is the Christ.”[48]

What does “Christian order” mean? Attention is required here, because there is no return to substantial conceptions of divine right or natural law in Schmitt. His idea of order is spatial, based on the containment of war made possible by the jus publicum Europaeum. Hobbes was, for Schmitt, the exemplary author of the jus publicum Europaeum, since he was the one who conceptually elaborated its fundamental agency in the Leviathan, namely the modern sovereign state. For Schmitt, Hobbes’ idea of the state was originally devised in order to put an end to religious civil war – and by “religious civil war” we have to understand the type of a war based on theological positions, whether religious or secular. The sovereign decision is that which puts an end to disorder, not by appeal to any substantial and transcendent ideas of truth and law, but as a purely formal criterion. The appeal to a substantial order external to the state itself was the very basis of potestas indirecta.

But then, how to understand Schmitt’s following affirmation in the 1963 notes (Hinweise) to The Concept of the Political:

The much admired system of Thomas Hobbes leaves a door open to transcendence. The truth that “Jesus is the Christ”, which Hobbes so often and so emphatically stated as his faith and confession, is a truth of public faith, public reason, and public worship in which the citizen participates.[49]

As Schmitt goes on to expand:

But this is not to raise the individual-psychological question of Thomas Hobbes’ subjective conviction, but the basic systematic problem of his whole political doctrine, which by no means closes the door to transcendence. It is the question of the interchangeability or non-interchangeability of the sentence, that Jesus is the Christ.[50]

Do we have here, in 1963, an admission by Schmitt of a transcendent order on which the state is grounded in a substantial way? This is not the case. There is no retreat from his theory of decisionism. How then to reconcile Schmitt’s decisionism and this idea of an openness to transcendence based on Christian faith? This is precisely where the notion of the katechon comes into play. A key to understanding this lies in a decisive passage from the Glossarium from 1949:

The most important sentence of Thomas Hobbes remains: Jesus is the Christ. The power of such a sentence is still effective if it is pushed to the edge of the conceptual system by which thought is structured, yes apparently even pushed outside of the conceptual sphere. This deportation (Abschiebung) is a process analogous to the cultification (Verkultung) of Christ, undertaken by Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor. Hobbes enunciates and scientifically grounds what Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor does: rendering Christ’s effect in the social and political domains harmless; to de-anarchize Christianity, while leaving it with a certain legitimizing effect in the background and, in any case, not to do without it. A clever tactician does not forego anything, unless it is completely unusable.[51]

It is not unreasonable to entertain the hypothesis that the way in which the reference to the Grand Inquisitor is employed, while not entirely discarding its importance, reflects a certain cynical attitude toward Christianity that Schmitt would later abandon. In his later work, the figure of the Grand Inquisitor will be replaced by the figure of the katechon. In the 1963 Hinweise, Schmitt explicitly rejects the idea that Hobbes’ affirmation of the Christian truth consisted in a tactical declaration.[52] Still, the notion that the Christian truth must be de-anarchized and pushed to the extreme edge of the conceptual system, while maintaining a legitimizing effect, retains its validity. In this sense, the defining action of the Grand Inquisitor is transferred to the katechon.

In Schmitt’s thought, the katechon is an eschatological notion whose function consists in the restrainment of disorder. The most extreme form of disorder for Schmitt is total war, of which civil war is the paradigm. In Political Theology II, Schmitt clearly admits the potentially subversive effect of Christianity when directly applied to the social and political domains as an attempt at bringing about the kingdom of heaven on earth, of “immanentizing the eschaton,” to employ Eric Voegelin’s expression. This “revolutionary” potential of Christianity – the false Christ which comes before “His glorious return on the Day of Judgement” – is that which needs to be staved off by the Grand Inquisitor. It is this (un)political messianism and millennialism which, translated in eschatological and political–theological figures, signifies, for Schmitt, the reign of the Antichrist.

Schmitt’s primary faith is in the katechon as the metapolitical and metastatic condition of possibility of the political.[53] The belief in Christ lies at the extreme edge of the conceptual system and is politically neutralized. The Hobbesian state has the truth of Christ embedded in it at the outermost edge. Since its effect is katechontic, since it averts civil war/total war – by containing it metastatically within itself – it has the Christian eschatological truth embedded in it. The sovereign state in itself is Christian in a political–theological sense, i.e., according to the political form of the Christian aeon, not in a theocratic nor hierocratic manner. That is why the question to be asked, according to Schmitt, is if the truth of the state (“that Jesus is the Christ”) can be replaced by other truths, ideologies, or “values.” But this truth is not a declared belief, it is a structural truth of the state, an axiomatic truth of public reason and jurisprudence. This is also why decisionism is not negated, the order of the state is not determined by substantial or material contents, as in the case of the traditional divine right of kings or natural law, the decision is purely formal. But the fact of order and sovereignty and the mutual recognition of sovereign states, as an inheritance of the jus publicum Europaeum and of the jus reformandi, are historically Christian, that is to say, katechontic.

6 Mortal God

Peterson’s two verdicts on the impossibility of political theology had been: 1) Trinitarian theology is not monotheist in the political–theological sense and 2) the “eschatological reserve” of Christianity cannot be suppressed by the historicization of the kingdom of God. Schmitt does not sacralize history nor reject eschatology. Eschatology is retained under the dynamic form of the different dispensations and historical missions which, without ever coinciding with it, embody the katechon as a metapolitical and metastatic agency – as a “total historical presence.”[54] For Schmitt, no particular form can fully realize the katechon, there is only a multiplicity of variable and contingent historical–political forms which embody it.

With regard to Trinitarian theology, we have seen how Schmitt inscribes the stasiological figure of his friend/enemy distinction within the Trinity. But Schmitt goes one step further in the systemic exposition of his political–theological position when relating Trinitarianism to eschatology. When proposing his own interpretation of Goethe’s enigmatic dictum “Nemo contra deum nisi deus ipse,” he refers to the Gnostic distinction between a just and severe God of creation and a loving God of salvation at enmity with each other. Against Blumenberg, Schmitt asserts that the Gnostic dualism is not overcome by modernity and its radical process of detheologization and depoliticization;[55] on the contrary, it is only intensified in an extreme stasis and war of annihilation between tradition and modernity, which has its prototype in the enmity between the God of creation and the God of salvation. Modernity, as the secularized political–theological position of the God of salvation, culminating in the absolutely liberated this-worldly spirit of technicity, wages a war of absolute enmity on tradition and, subsequently, on theology and on every political form determined by the friend/enemy distinction. But in doing so, it reveals itself as a counter-theology, which is incapable of perceiving the dialectical opposition which determines it and incapable of taking its destructive work to the end and conceptually destroying its own unquestioned position in the process.

For Schmitt this position is itself only possible within Christian eschatology and possesses its political–theological principle in a type of political and revolutionary Christology which assumes a messianic guise by seeking the realization of the kingdom of God in this world. The divinization of man is presupposed by the humanity of God in Christ, which is perceived metaphysically and political-theologically as the archetype of Man divinized, from whom proceed all forms of divinity and God himself as products. Yet, for Schmitt, this radical form of theologized humanity – as the extreme result of the modern process of detheologization – is also the most extreme form of depoliticization, whose consequence is the reduction of all divergent views to the status of inhumanity and infra-humanity.

The Gnostic dualism – corresponding to the absolute position of the friend/enemy distinction – is implicitly present in the Trinity, with the distinction between Father and Son, which is dialectically conceived as the opposition and stasis between God and Man. Yet, for Schmitt, this stasis of the two natures is overcome by their metastatic unity in the second person, the God–Man Christ.[56] The Gnostic revolutionary potential of the Son is neutralized by the union of two natures in Christ[57] – the principle itself of political theology.[58]

In eschatological terms, this metastatic unity presents itself in the guise of the katechon. The katechon is two-sided, it doubly relates to the two political–theological features of Christ: it simultaneously “contains” the revolutionary and messianic stasis and it “contains” the kingdom of God, never realized in this world.[59] The katechon relates both to the Antichrist and to Christ in his parousia, since by holding back the reign of the Antichrist, it simultaneously prevents the final coming of Christ. The human and the divine aspects of Christ are reflected in the split between the political and the theological, which is united in the katechon.[60] This unity is not a dialectical union of reconciliation but a bipolar double movement of restrainment and containment. Metastasis, as a metastate (in Latin, status has the same formation as the Greek stasis), is simultaneously contention and containment – containment by contention and contention by containment.

As we have seen, Schmitt understands the confession of faith in Christ in a political–theological manner as the truth of the Hobbesian state, i.e., of the “Mortal God.”[61] The state as a mortal god is the secularization of the corpus mysticum of the Church as corpus Christi. What Schmitt designated as the “transposition of concepts” from the Church to the state[62] has its vanishing point in the transference of the representation of the person of Christ by the Church to the transcendent truth of the state as mortal god.[63] This is, for Schmitt, the result and presupposition of the massive metaphysical transference from theology to jurisprudence. What is common to the Church and to the state is the eschatological horizon in which their juristic concepts operate. For Schmitt, this is the political–theological truth of the Christian aeon inaugurated by the Christ-event which persists in the epoch of secularization.

7 Conclusion

In his assumption of a fundamental dualism between political theology and political philosophy and in an attempt to safeguard the atheological essence of political philosophy, Meier exaggerates the theological aspects of Schmitt’s thought, to the point of conceiving of him as a theologian first and foremost. All the authors and researchers who see Schmitt as a jurist would be gullible to the mystification and strategic obfuscation that Schmitt would have operated to hide the fundamentally theological content of his thought and work. Furthermore, even though he ostensibly rejects what he calls the “confessional classification,” Meier’s thesis is ambiguous. It is unclear whether he regards Schmitt’s political theology as being grounded in the traditional Catholic faith or in a more singular faith in a providentialist theology of History, abstractly based on Christianity and on the event of the Incarnation. At no point does Meier discuss the issue of determining whether and how this last view can be considered theological in a rigorous sense of the term. Finally, and most importantly, Meier’s thesis is abrupt and does not give sufficient importance to the turns, the shifts, the advances and retreats, and the complexities of Schmitt’s political theology. This lack of forethought becomes evident in his reductionistic theological understanding of political theology.

The proof a contrario that Schmitt is not a theological thinker, but a political thinker, and that political theology needs to be understood, at its core, as a theologization and a metaphysics of the political is visibly manifest by the fact that Schmitt’s crowning theological speculation relies on bending the words and the meaning of Saint Gregory of Nazianzus’ sentence on monarchy and stasis. In the passage referred to by both Peterson and Schmitt, Gregory does not state that “the one” is “always” in uproar against itself as a defining trait of the orthodox dogma of the Trinity.[64] Gregory’s affirmation is negative and conditional, the stasis that he refers to is not a characteristic of the orthodox dogma of the Trinity, but of a specific heretical interpretation of the Trinity, one where the monarchy is “limited to one Person.”[65] For the Church Father, the idea of the divine monarchy limited to one person was the heretical doctrine of Eunomius, a form of extreme Arianism that entirely denied the consubstantiality of the Trinity and thus introduced factionalism and division within the Trinity. Eunomianism was the doctrine where the monarchy, God as the “one principle,” would be limited to the “one person” of the Father, thereby excluding the Son and the Holy Spirit from the divine essence and generating a plurality and division of essences, as well as relations of opposition and subordination within the Trinity.[66]

Schmitt projects the political in its stasiological figure onto the theological dogma of the Trinity and presents it as the core of the doctrine, according to his own understanding. The conspicuous absence of the Holy Spirit in his theological speculations shows, as well, that his crypto-ditheist view of the Trinitarian dogma was conditioned by the Gnostic dualism, in which he saw the stasiological climax of his own concept of the political. In doing so, he radically rejected Peterson’s assertion – and of all orthodox Trinitarianism – of an absence of analogy between God and creation. Metapolitics is converted into metaphysics, and stasis, as the extreme intensity of the political, is erected to the theological status of the absolute as metastasis. This metastatic principle shows itself as the structure of the katechon, the true Schmittian credo and symbolo pisteōs, whereby contention becomes the principle of containment. And, ultimately, this principle is identified with Christ, as the unity of divine and human, understood as a complexio oppositorum, a metaphysical unity of two without dialectical synthesis.

Even though Schmitt misrepresented the Trinitarian dogma in order to raise the concept of the political to a theological status, his conception of the katechon maintained an effective relation with the Christian theology of history. Yet, the decisive question – and it was a question that plagued Schmitt to the end – is whether the relegation of the parousia to the outermost edge of the political, thus deprived of every real political effect, could make Schmitt a “hastener against his will.” The only way in which Schmitt could conceive of the immediate, non-represented, presence of Christ in this world was exactly that of (un)political millennialism or messianism, as the political ideal of the realization of the kingdom of God on earth. Because of this, Schmitt’s katechon can indeed be seen as indistinguishable from the Grand Inquisitor, who, in “containing” evil, keeps away the advent of the parousia and thus risks becoming the enemy of Christ. But whether the katechon is the friend or the enemy of Christ remains an open question, at least until final judgment.

Acknowledgments

I thank Luke Collison and Viktoria Huegel for their help and suggestions.

  1. Funding information: This publication is funded with National Funds through the FCT/MCTES – Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia/Ministério da Ciência, Tecnologia e Ensino Superior (Foundation for Science and Technology/Ministry for Science, Technology and Higher Education – Portugal), in the framework of the Project of the Institute of Philosophy with the reference UIDB/00502/2020.

  2. Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.

References

Agamben, Giorgio. The Kingdom and the Glory: For a Theological Genealogy of Economy and Government. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011.Search in Google Scholar

Arvidsson, Matilda. “From Teleology to Eschatology: The Katechon and the Political Theology of the International Law of Belligerent Occupation.” In The Contemporary Relevance of Carl Schmitt, edited by Matilda Arvidsson, Leïla Brännström, and Panu Minkkinen, 223–36. London/New York: Routledge, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Böckenförde, Ernst-Wolfgang. “The Concept of the Political: A Key to Understanding Carl Schmitt’s Constitutional Theory.” Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 10:1 (1997), 5–19.Search in Google Scholar

Böckenförde, Ernst-Wolfgang. “Political Theory and Political Theology.” In Religion, Law and Democracy. Selected Writings, edited by Mirjam Künkler and Tine Stein, 248–58. New York: Oxford University Press, 2020.Search in Google Scholar

Bourdin, Bernard. “Carl Schmitt: Un Contre-Messianisme Théologico-Politique?” Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques 98 (2014), 241–59.Search in Google Scholar

Bray, Dennis. “Gregory Of Nazianzus’ Trinitarian Argument in Oration 23.” TheoLogica 4:2 (2020), 138–60.Search in Google Scholar

Büttgen, Philippe. “Théologie Politique. Le problème, le système et la science (1925-1970).” In Théologie Politique et Sciences Sociales. Autour d’Erik Peterson, edited by Philippe Büttgen and Alain Rauwel, 147–70. Paris: Éditions EHESS, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Cacciari, Massimo. The Withholding Power: An Essay on Political Theology, translated by Edi Pucci and Harry Marandi. London: Bloomsbury, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Chen, Jianhong. “What Is Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology?” Interpretation 33:2 (2006), 153–76.Search in Google Scholar

Geréby, György. “Political Theology Versus Theological Politics: Erik Peterson and Carl Schmitt.” New German Critique 35:3 (2008), 7–33.Search in Google Scholar

Geréby, György. “The Angels of the Nations. Is a National Christianity Possible?” In Across the Mediterranean – Along the Nile, edited by Tamás A. Bács, Ádám Bollók, and Tivadar Vida, 819–47. Budapest: Archaeolingua Foundation, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Geréby, György. “The Theology of Carl Schmitt.” Politeja 72 (2021), 21–49.Search in Google Scholar

Gourgouris, Stathis. “Political Theology as Monarchical Thought.” Constellations 23:2 (2016), 145–59.Search in Google Scholar

Gregory of Nazianzus. “Select Orations.” In The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, vol. VII, translated by C. G. Browne and J. E. Swallow. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 1952.Search in Google Scholar

Groh, Ruth. Arbeit an der Heillosigkeit der Welt. Zur politisch-theologischen Mythologie Carl Schmitts. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1998.Search in Google Scholar

Herrera, Hugo Eduardo. “La caracterización de la teología política de Carl Schmitt por parte de Heinrich Meier.” Revista de Estudios Políticos 159 (2013), 13–37.Search in Google Scholar

Herrero, Montserrat. The Political Discourse of Carl Schmitt: A Mystic of Order. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Herrero, Montserrat. “Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology: The Magic of a Phrase.” In Political Theology in Medieval and Early Modern Europe: Discourses Rites and Representations, edited by Montserrat Herrero, Jaume Aurell, and Angela C. Miceli Stout, 23–42. Turnhout: Brepols Publishers, 2017.Search in Google Scholar

Hohendahl, Peter. “Political Theology Revisited: Carl Schmitt’s Postwar Reassessment.” Konturen 1:1 (2008). 10.5399/uo/konturen.1.1.1266.Search in Google Scholar

Hollerich, Michael. “Catholic Anti-Liberalism in Weimar: Political Theology and its Critics.” In The Weimar Moment: Liberalism, Political Theology and Law, edited by Leonard V. Kaplan and Rudy Koshar, 17–46. Plymouth: Lexington Books, 2012.Search in Google Scholar

Hollerich, Michael. Making Christian History: Eusebius of Caesarea and his Readers. Oakland: University of California Press, 2021.Search in Google Scholar

Kervègan, Jean-François. “¿Qué significa ser un teólogo de la jurisprudencia?” Deus Mortalis 9 (2009), 91–106.Search in Google Scholar

Koskenniemi, Martti. “International Law as Political Theology: How to Read Nomos der Erde?” Constellations 11:4 (2004), 492–511.Search in Google Scholar

Langford, Peter and Ian Bryan. “Beyond the Jurist as a Theologian of Legal Science: The Question of Carl Schmitt and the International Legal Order.” In The Contemporary Relevance of Carl Schmitt, edited by Matilda Arvidsson, Leïla Brännström, and Panu Minkkinen, 208–22. London/New York: Routledge, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Lievens, Matthias. “Theology without God.” Bijdragen 72:4 (2011), 408–31.Search in Google Scholar

Lievens, Matthias. “Carl Schmitt’s Metapolitics.” Constellations 20:1 (2013), 121–37.Search in Google Scholar

Lievens, Matthias. “Carl Schmitt’s Concept of History.” In The Oxford Handbook of Carl Schmitt, edited by Jens Meierhenrich and Oliver Simons, 401–25. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.Search in Google Scholar

Maier, Hans. “Erik Peterson Und Das Problem Der Politischen Theologie.” Zeitschrift Für Politik 38:1 (1991), 33–46.Search in Google Scholar

Manemann, Jürgen. Carl Schmitt und die Politische Theologie. Politischer Anti-Monotheismus. Münster: Aschendorff, 2002.Search in Google Scholar

Maritain, Jacques. The Twilight of Civilization. London: Sheed & Ward, 1946.Search in Google Scholar

Meier, Heinrich. The Lesson of Carl Schmitt: Four Chapters on the Distinction Between Political Theology and Political Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011.Search in Google Scholar

Meuter, Günter. Der Katechon. Zu Carl Schmitts Fundamentalistischer Kritik der Zeit. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1994.Search in Google Scholar

Monod, Jean-Claude. “Le Débat Schmitt-Peterson: Une ‘Polémique Bien Ajustée.’” In Théologie et Politique: Une Relation Ambivalente, edited by Jean-Luc Blaquart and Bernard Bourdin, 139–58. Paris: L’Harmattan, 2009.Search in Google Scholar

Müller, Jan. “Carl Schmitt – An Occasional Nationalist?” History of European Ideas 23:1 (1997), 19–34.Search in Google Scholar

Nault, François. “Entre la Théologisation du Politique et la Politisation du Théologique: en Lisant Carl Schmitt.” Laval Théologique et Philosophique 63:2 (2007), 225–43.Search in Google Scholar

Noack, Paul. Carl Schmitt: eine Biographie. Frankfurt/Main: Ullstein, 1996.Search in Google Scholar

Ojakangas, Mika. “Carl Schmitt and the Sacred Origins of Law.” Telos 147 (2009), 34–54.Search in Google Scholar

Ojakangas, M., 2007. “A Terrifying World Without an Exterior: Carl Schmitt and the Metaphysics of International (dis)Order.” In The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt, edited by Louiza Odysseos and Fabio Petito, 217–33. London/New York: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Palaver, Wolfgang. “Carl Schmitt on Nomos and Space.” Telos 106 (1996), 105–27.Search in Google Scholar

Palaver, Wolfgang. “Carl Schmitt, Mythologue Politique.” Afterword to Le Léviathan dans la Doctrine de l'État de Thomas Hobbes, edited by Carl Schmitt, 191–247. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 2002.Search in Google Scholar

Palaver, Wolfgang. “Carl Schmitt’s ‘Apocalyptic’ Resistance against Global Civil War.” In Politics & Apocalypse, edited by Robert G. Hamerton-Kelly, 69–94. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2007.Search in Google Scholar

Paléologue, Théodore. Sous l’Oeil du Grand Inquisiteur. Carl Schmitt et l’Héritage de la Théologie Politique. Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 2004.Search in Google Scholar

Peterson, Erik. “Monotheism as a Political Problem.” In Theological Tractates, edited and translated by Michael J. Hollerich, 68–105. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011.Search in Google Scholar

Rae, Gavin. “The Theology of Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology.” Political Theology 17:6 (2016), 555–72.Search in Google Scholar

Rauwel, Alain. “La Théologie au Tourment du Siècle. Destins d’Erik Peterson.” In Théologie Politique et Sciences Sociales. Autour d’Erik Peterson, edited by Philippe Büttgen and Alain Rauwel, 23–8. Paris: Éditions EHESS, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Roberts, Aaron B. “Carl Schmitt – Political Theologian?” The Review of Politics 77:3 (2015), 449–74.Search in Google Scholar

Rasch, William. “Conflict as a Vocation: Carl Schmitt and the Possibility of Politics.” Theory, Culture & Society 17:6 (2000), 1–32.Search in Google Scholar

Ruggieri, Giuseppe. “Dios y Poder. ¿Funcionalidad Política del Monoteísmo?” Concilium 197 (1985), 29–42.Search in Google Scholar

de Sá, Alexandre Franco. “Teologia Política entre Império e Estado.” Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 75:3 (2019), 1459–88.Search in Google Scholar

Schmidt, Anna. “The Problem of Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology.” Interpretation 36:3 (2009), 219–52.Search in Google Scholar

Schmidt, Christoph. “The Leviathan Crucified. A Critical Introduction to Jacob Taubes’ ‘The Leviathan as Mortal God.’” Political Theology 19:3 (2018), 172–92.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. “Die vollendete Reformation: Bemerkungen und Hinweise zu neuen Leviathan-Interpretationen.” Der Staat 4:1 (1965), 51–69.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, translated by Ellen Kennedy. Cambridge/London: MIT Press, 1985.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Der Begriff des Politischen. Synoptische Darstellung der Texte. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Glossarium: Aufzeichnungen der Jahre 1947-1951, edited by Eberhard Medem. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1991.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Theodor Däublers “Nordlicht.” Drei Studien über die Elemente, den Geist und die Aktualität des Werkes. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1991.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. On the Three Types of Juristic Thought, translated by Joseph W. Bendersky. Westport: Praeger Publishers, 2005.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, translated by George Schwab. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum. New York: Telos Press Publishing, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Roman Catholicism and Political form, translated by G. L. Ulmen. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. The Concept of the Political, translated by George Schwab. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure of a Political Symbol, translated by George Schwab and Erna Hilfstein. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Theory of the Partisan: Intermediate Commentary on the Concept of the Political, translated by Gary L. Ulmen. New York: Telos Press Publishing, 2012.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology II: The Myth of the Closure of Any Political Theology, translated by Michael Hoelzl and Graham Ward. Cambridge: Polity, 2016.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl. Ex Captivitate Salus. Experiences, 1945-47, edited by Andreas Kalyvas and Federico Finchelstein, translated by Matthew Hannah. Cambridge: Polity, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Schmitt, Carl, Lars Vinx, and Samuel Garrett Zeitlin. Carl Schmitt’s Early Legal-Theoretical Writings: Statute and Judgment and the Value of the State and the Significance of the Individual. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 2021.Search in Google Scholar

Senellart, Michel. “À propos des anges des nations. Le problème théologico-politique du nationalisme selon Erik Peterson.” In Théologie politique et sciences sociales. Autour d’Erik Peterson, edited by Philippe Büttgen and Alain Rauwel, 193–210. Paris: Éditions EHESS, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Storme, Tristan. “Peut-on Lire Erik Peterson sans Carl Schmitt? L’ombre du Théorème de la Sécularisation.” Revue de l’histoire des Religions 3:3 (2021), 423–34.Search in Google Scholar

Strong, Tracy B. “The Sacred Quality of the Political. Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul.” Politisches Denken 20 (2010), 245–94.Search in Google Scholar

Tenaillon, Nicolas. “Peterson et le Recours à la Théologie Politique.” Laval Théologique et Philosophique 63:2 (2007), 245–57.Search in Google Scholar

Vatter, Miguel. “The Political Theology of Carl Schmitt.” In The Oxford handbook of Carl Schmitt, edited by Jens Meierhenrich and Oliver Simons, 245–68. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.Search in Google Scholar

Vatter, Miguel. “‘Only a God Can Resist a God.’ Political Theology between Polytheism and Gnosticism.” Political Theology 20:6 (2019), 472–97.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2022-07-30
Revised: 2023-02-19
Accepted: 2023-03-21
Published Online: 2023-06-06

© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 1.12.2023 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/opth-2022-0228/html
Scroll to top button