Abstract
Peirce holds that our logic should be the basis for our metaphysics. He also thinks that facts and propositions are structurally isomorphic. However, unlike many theorists who take propositions such as snow is white and grass is green as their paradigmatic examples, Peirce takes it rains (Latin: pleurit) and similar propositions as his paradigmatic examples. I explore how his analysis of such propositions and the way in which they convey meaning becomes more complex from 1895 to 1909, how this impacts his metaphysics, and how he can claim that something like the common environment of two interlocutors can itself be an index.
References
Atkin, Albert. 2005. Peirce on the index and indexical reference. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 41(4). 161–188.Search in Google Scholar
Atkins, Richard Kenneth. 2006. Re-structuring the sciences: Peirce’s categories and his classifications of the sciences. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 42(4). 483–500.10.1353/csp.2007.0000Search in Google Scholar
Atkins, Richard Kenneth. 2016a. Peirce on facts and true propositions. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24(6). 1176–1192.10.1080/09608788.2016.1185390Search in Google Scholar
Atkins, Richard Kenneth. 2016b. Peirce and the conduct of life: Sentiment and instinct in ethics and religion. New York: Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781316676240Search in Google Scholar
Bellucci, Francesco. 2015. Exploring peirce’s speculative grammar: The immediate object of a sign. Sign Systems Studies 43(4). 399–418.10.12697/SSS.2015.43.4.02Search in Google Scholar
Hookway, Christopher. 2002. … a sort of composite photograph: Pragmatism, ideas, and schematism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 38(1/2). 29–45.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199588381.003.0008Search in Google Scholar
Lane, Robert. 2009. Persons, signs, animals: A Peircean account of personhood. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 45(1). 1–26.10.2979/tra.2009.45.1.1Search in Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles & Lady Victoria Welby. 1977. Semiotic and significs. Charles S. Hardwick (ed.). Bloomington: Indianapolis University Press. [Reference to this work will be designated SS followed by page number.].Search in Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1931–1966. The collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, vol. 8. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. W. Burks (eds.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Reference to Peirce’s papers will be designated CP followed by volume and paragraph number.].Search in Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1967. Manuscripts in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, as identified by Richard Robin, Annotated catalogue of the papers of Charles S. Peirce. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. [Reference to Peirce’s manuscripts will be designated MS or L.].Search in Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1982. Writings of Charles S. Peirce, vol. 6. M. Fisch, E. Moore & C. Kloesel (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to Peirce’s writings will be designated W followed by volume and page number.].Search in Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1998. Essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings, vol. 2. 1893–1913. Peirce Edition Project (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to vol. 2 of Essential Peirce will be designated EP 2.].Search in Google Scholar
Stjernfelt, Frederik. 2014. Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of the dicisign. Boston: Docent Press.10.1007/s11229-014-0406-5Search in Google Scholar
© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston