Skip to content
Licensed Unlicensed Requires Authentication Published by De Gruyter Mouton March 20, 2019

Index as scaffold to logical and final interpretants: Compulsive urges and modal submissions

  • Donna E. West EMAIL logo
From the journal Semiotica

Abstract

This inquiry capitalizes on the relational character of Peirce’s index. Its evolution from object finder in the physical world, to enhancer of communication between minds, to modal/perspectival coordinator is examined. Its relational character organizes events into episodes, and obviates perspectival alterations in dialogic reasoning. This shift demonstrates Peirce’s last word regarding Index: a sign intrinsically dialogic, whose interpretants increase levels of consciousness, and advance communicational interaction by commanding self/others to believe/act in novel ways.

Its power to coordinate specific, vivid images provides index with the means to suggest novel propositions, assertions, and arguments. Peirce memorializes this relational role by characterizing index as Dicisign, and afterward as Pheme (1904, CP 8.334–8.339; 1906, MS 295: 26; 1908, EP 2: 489–490). As truncated Argument, Index provides the catalyst for interpreters to determine the meaning of interpretants be they Energetic, Logical or Final. Its non-symbolic character provides interpreters the impetus to utilize inferencing powers to attach meanings, thus expanding kinds of interpretants. Index constitutes the most diverse semiotic tool for interpreters – it traces subtle deontic, epistemic, and logical shifts. In situating and resituating events in time, place, and participatedness, Index aptly measures actual and potential shifts in affect, attention, location, credibility, and the like.

Ultimately, index integrates the logical with the phenomenological and the empirical with the semiotic – when it deploys relational operators to trace event templates and to predict participant’s perspectives. As such, interpreters restructure thought and action and recommend sound courses of action for diverse event participants.

References

Atkin, Albert. 2005. Peirce on the index and indexical reference. Transations of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41(1). 161–168.Search in Google Scholar

Bellucci, Francesco. 2014. “Logic, considered as semeiotic”: On Peirce’s philosophy of logic. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 50(4). 523–547.10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.50.4.523Search in Google Scholar

Houser, Nathan. 2016. Social minds and the fixation of belief. In Donna West & Myrdene Anderson (eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s concept of habit: Before and beyond consciousness. 379–400. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-319-45920-2_21Search in Google Scholar

Kilpinen, Erkki. 2016. In what sense exactly is Peirce’s habit-concept revolutionary? In Donna West & Myrdene Anderson (eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s concept of habit: Before and beyond consciousness. 199–214. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-319-45920-2_12Search in Google Scholar

Merrell, Floyd. 2001. Peirce’s concept of the sign. In Paul Cobley (ed.), The Routledge companion to semiotics and linguistics. 28–39. London: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles & Lady Victoria Welby. 1977. Semiotic and significs. Charles S. Hardwick (ed.). Bloomington: Indianapolis University Press. [Reference to this work will be designated SS followed by page number.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1931–1966. The collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, vol. 8. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. W. Burks (eds.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Reference to Peirce’s papers will be designated CP followed by volume and paragraph number.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1967. Manuscripts in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, as identified by Richard Robin, Annotated catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. [Reference to Peirce’s manuscripts will be designated MS or L.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1976. The new elements of mathematics, vol. 4. C. Eisele (ed.). Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter; Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. [Reference to Peirce’s New Elements will be designated NEM followed by volume and page number.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1982. Writings of Charles S. Peirce, vol. 6. M. Fisch, E. Moore & C. Kloesel (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to Peirce’s writings will be designated W followed by volume and page number.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1992. Essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings, vol. 1, 1867–1893. N. Houser & C. Kloesel (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to vol. 1 of Essential Peirce will be designated EP 1.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1997. Pragmatism as a principle and method of right thinking: The 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism. Patricia Ann Turrisi (ed.). Albany: SUNY Press, 1997. [Reference to Peirce’s Pragmatism will be designated PPM followed by volume and paragraph number.].Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1998. Essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings, vol. 2, 1893–1913. Peirce Edition Project (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to vol. 2 of Essential Peirce will be designated EP 2.].Search in Google Scholar

Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko. 2004. The endoporeutic method. In J. Queiroz (ed.). Digital encyclopedia of Charles S. Peirce. http://www.digitalpeirce.fee.unicamp.br/pietarinen/endo.html (accessed 20 February 2019).Search in Google Scholar

Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko. 2006. Signs of logic: Peircean themes of the philosophy of language, games, and communication. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Roberts, Donald D. 1973. The existential graphs of Charles S. Peirce. The Hague: Mouton.10.1515/9783110226225Search in Google Scholar

Short, Thomas L. 1996. Interpreting Peirce’s interpretant: A response to Lalor, Liszka, and Meyers. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32(4). 488–541.Search in Google Scholar

Short, Thomas L. 2007. Peirce’s theory of signs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511498350Search in Google Scholar

Stjernfelt, Frederik. 2014. Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of dicisigns. Boston: Docent Press.10.1007/s11229-014-0406-5Search in Google Scholar

Stjernfelt, Frederik. 2015. Dicisigns: Peirce’s semiotic doctrine of propositions. Synthese 2015. 1–36.10.1007/s11229-014-0406-5Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. 2013. Deictic imaginings: Semiosis at work and at play. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-642-39443-0Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. 2014. Perspective-switching as event affordance: The ontogeny of abductive reasoning. Cognitive Semiotics 7(2). 149–176.10.1515/cogsem-2014-0011Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. 2015. The work of secondness as habit in the development of early schemes. Public Journal of Semiotics 6(2). 1–13.10.37693/pjos.2015.6.13270Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. 2016a. Dialogue as habit-taking in Peirce’s continuum: The call to absolute chance. Dialogue 54(4). 685–702.10.1017/S0012217315000773Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. 2016b. Indexical scaffolds to habit-formation. In Donna West & Myrdene Anderson (eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s concept of habit: Before and beyond consciousness. 215–240. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-319-45920-2_13Search in Google Scholar

West, Donna. under review. Individuating in undifferentiated space: Trends within normative versus blind populations.Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2019-03-20
Published in Print: 2019-05-07

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 11.12.2023 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/sem-2018-0085/html
Scroll to top button