Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Apeiron

A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science

Ed. by Wildberg, Christian / Morison, Benjamin

Online
ISSN
2156-7093
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Ahead of print

Issues

Reassessing Epictetus’ Opinion of Divination

Erlend D. MacGillivray
Published Online: 2019-05-31 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0013

Abstract

In recent years substantial effort has been expended by scholars to better understand the nature of the ancient interest in divination. This study will argue that the Stoic philosopher Epictetus’ views of divination have been largely overlooked and mistakenly defined by his modern interpreters. While often portrayed as being opposed to the art, it is proposed that he envisages divination can be beneficially employed: namely in highlighting certain moral actions, and in motivating individuals to commence philosophical study.

Keywords: Epictetus; Divination; Oracular; Stoicism

References

  • Babbitt, F. C. 1936. Plutarch’s Moralia, Loeb Classical Library 306. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Bar-Kochva, B. 2010. The Image of the Jews in Greek Literature. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar

  • Bobzien, S. 1999. Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Bowden, H. 2005. Classical Athens and the Delphic Oracle: Divination and Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Brouwer, R., “Stoic Sympathy.” Draft paper, Oxford Philosophical Concepts at the Jepson School of Leadership, University of Richmond. Accessed 08 Nov. 2018 <http://jepson.richmond.edu/conferences/sympathy2012/Brouwer-Stoic%20Sympathy.pdf> 2012.Google Scholar

  • Busine, A. 2005. Paroles d’Apollon pratiques et traditions oraculaires dans l’Antiquite tardive. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar

  • Cohoon, J. W. 1932. Dio Chrysostom, Discourses 1–11, Loeb Classical Library 257. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Colish, M. L. 1984. The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar

  • Danzig, G. 2010. Apologizing for Socrates. How Plato and Xenophon Created Our Socrates. Lanham MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar

  • Dobbin, R. 1998. Discourses Book 1: Claredon Later Ancient Philosophers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Downing, F. 1992. Cynics and Christian Origins. London: T & T Clark.Google Scholar

  • Doyle, J. 2012. “Socratic Methods.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 42 (2): 39–75.Google Scholar

  • Flower, M. A. 2009. The Seer in Ancient Greece. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar

  • Fontenrose, J. 1978. Delphic Oracles: Its Responses and Operations — With a Catalogue of Responses. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar

  • Gabor, G. 2014. “When Should A Philosopher Consult Divination? Epictetus and Simplicius on Fate and What Is up to Us?” In Fate, Providence and Moral Responsibility in Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern Thought: Studies in Honour of Carlos Steel, edited by P. d’Hoine, and G. V. Riel, 325–40. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar

  • Gigon, O. 1946. “Antike Erzahlungen uber die Berufung zur Philosophic.” Museum Helveticum 3: 1–21.Google Scholar

  • Gill, C. 2013. “Cynicism and Stoicism.” In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, edited by R. Crisp, 93–112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Gill, C., and R. Hard. 1995. The Discourses, the Handbook, Fragments. London: Everyman.Google Scholar

  • Graf, F. 2009. Apollo. Gods and Heroes of the Ancient World. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

  • Hankinson, R. J. 1988. “Stoicism, Science and Divination.” Apeiron 21 (2): 123–60.Google Scholar

  • Jedan, C. 2009. Stoic Virtues: Chrysippus and the Religious Character of Stoic Ethics. London: Continuum.Google Scholar

  • Johnson, B. E. 2012. “Socrates, Heracles and the Deflation of Roles in Epictetus.” Ancient Philosophy 32 (1): 125–45.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Johnson, L. T. 2009. Among the Gentiles: Greco-Roman Religion and Christianity. New Haven CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar

  • Lipsey, R. 2001. Have You Been to Delphi: Tales of the Ancient Oracle for Modern Minds. Albany NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar

  • Long, A. A. 2002. Epictetus: A Stoic and Socratic Guide to Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Mikalson, J. D. 2010. Greek Popular Religion in Greek Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Schofield, M. 2007. “Epictetus on Cynicism.” In The Philosophy of Epictetus, edited by T. Scaltsas, and A. S. Mason, 71–86. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sellars, J. 2003. The Art of Living: The Stoics on the Nature and Function of Philosophy. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar

  • Sevenster, J. N. 1966. “Education or Conversion: Epictetus and the Gospels.” Novum Testamentum 8 (2): 247–62.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Struck, P. T. 2016. Divination and Human Nature: A Cognitive History of Intuition in Classical Antiquity. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

  • Tortzen, C. G. 2002. “Know Thyself- A Note on the Success of A Delphic Saying.” In Noctes Atticae: Articles on Greco-Roman Antiquity and Its Nachleben, edited by P. Flensted-Jensen, T. H. Nielsen, A. Schwartz, and C. H. Tortzen, 302–14. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum.Google Scholar

  • Williams, G. D. 2012. The Cosmic Viewpoint: A Study of Seneca’s Natural Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Xenakis, I. 1969. Epictetus Philosopher-Therapist. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2019-05-31


Citation Information: Apeiron, ISSN (Online) 2156-7093, ISSN (Print) 0003-6390, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0013.

Export Citation

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter Inc., Boston/Berlin.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in