Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Apeiron

A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science

Ed. by Wildberg, Christian / Morison, Benjamin

Online
ISSN
2156-7093
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Ahead of print

Issues

The Physiology of Phantasmata in Aristotle: between Sensation and Digestion

Claire Bubb
  • Corresponding author
  • Institute for the Study of the Ancient World, New York University, 15 E 84th St, New York, NY 10028, USA
  • Email
  • Other articles by this author:
  • De Gruyter OnlineGoogle Scholar
Published Online: 2018-10-16 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0015

Abstract

In this article, I foreground the physiology of phantasia in Aristotle, which has been comparatively understudied. In the first section, I offer a new interpretation of the relationship between aisthēmata (sense perceptions) and phantasmata, based on passages in the De Anima and the Parva Naturalia, and for a nuanced understanding of their respective substrates in the body, which I argue to be connate pneuma and blood. In the second section, I draw out the ramifications of this physiological presence of phantasmata in the blood and compare the integration of phantasmata into a person or animal’s experiential history with the process of digestion. Both processes, I contend, require internalization of foreign elements as well as their optimal organization; more strikingly, both processes occur in the same substance, in the same location, and, perhaps, at the same time.

Keywords: Aristotle; phantasia; sensation; digestion; dreams

References

  • Althoff, J. 1992. Warm und kalt, flüssig und fest bei Aristoteles. Die Elementarqualitäten in den zoologischen Schriften. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.Google Scholar

  • Barnes, J. 1975. Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Beare, J. I. 1906. Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition: From Alcmaeon to Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Beare, J. I. and Ross, G. R. T. 1908. The Parva Naturalia. Oxford: Clarendon Press (reprinted in The Works of Aristotle Translated into English, vol. III, edited by W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1931).Google Scholar

  • Bloch, D. 2007. Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Text, Translation, Interpretation, and Reception in Western Scholasticism. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar

  • Bolton, R. 1997. “The Material Cause: Matter and Explanation in Aristotle’s Natural Science.” In Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, edited by W. Kullman and S. Föllinger, 97–126. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.Google Scholar

  • Boylan, M. 2015. The Origins of Ancient Greek Science. Blood—A Philosophical Study. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar

  • Bubb, C. Forthcoming. “Blood Flow in Aristotle.” CQ.Google Scholar

  • Burnyeat, M. 1992. “Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? A Draft.” In Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, edited by M.C. Nussbaum and A.O. Rorty, 15–26. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Bylebyl, J. J. 1977. “Nutrition, Quantification, and Circulation.” BHM 51. 369–385.Google Scholar

  • Caston, V. 1996. “Why Aristotle Needs Imagination.” Phronesis 41 (1): 20–55.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Caston, V. 1998. “Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality.” Ph&PhenR 58. 249–298.Google Scholar

  • Caston, V. 2005. “The Spirit and the Letter: Aristotle on Perception.” In Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics in Ancient Thought: Themes from the Work of Richard Sorabji, edited by R. Salles, 245–320. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Caston, V. 2009. “Aristotle’s Psychology.” In A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, edited by M.L. Gill and P. Pellegrin, 316–346. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Code, A. 2015. “The ‘Matter’ of Sleep.” In Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science, edited by D. Ebrey, 11–45. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Corcilius, K., and P. Gregoric. 2013. “Aristotle’s Model of Animal Motion.” Phronesis 58. 52–97.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Ebrey, D. 2015. “Blood, Matter, and Necessity.” In Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science, edited by D. Ebrey, 61–76. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • van der Eijk, P. 1994. Aristoteles, Uber Traüme; Uber die Weissagung im Schlaf. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar

  • van der Eijk, P. 1997. “The Matter of Mind: Aristotle on the Biology of ‘Psychic’ Processes and the Bodily Aspects of Thinking.” In Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, edited by W. Kullmann and S. Föllinger, 231–258. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.Google Scholar

  • van der Eijk, P. 2000. “Aristotle’s Psycho-Physiological Account of the Soul-Body Relationship.” In Psyche and Soma: Physicians and Metaphysicians on the Mind-Body Problem from Antiquity to Enlightenment, edited by J.P. Wright and P. Potter, 57–78. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • van der Eijk, P. 2005. “Theoretical and Empirical Elements in Aristotle’s Treatment of Sleep, Dreams and Divination in Sleep.” In Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity, edited by J.P. Wright and P. Potter, 169–205. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Everson, S. 1997. Aristotle on Perception. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Everson, S. 2007. “The De Somno and Aristotle’s Explanation of Sleep.” CQ 57. 502–520.Google Scholar

  • Freudenthal, G. 1995. Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Freudenthal, J. 1863. Über den Begriff des Wortes ΦΑΝΤΑΣΙΑ bei Aristoteles. Göttingen: Verlag von Adalbert Rente.Google Scholar

  • Gallop, D. 1996. Aristotle. On Sleep and Dreams. A Text and Translation with Introduction, Notes, and Glossary. Warminster, UK: Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar

  • Gregoric, P. 2007. Aristotle on the Common Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Gregoric, P., and F. Grgic. 2006. “Aristotle’s Notion of Experience.” AGPh 88. 1–30.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hardie, W. F. R. 1964. “Aristotle’s Treatment of the Relation between the Soul and the Body.” PhilosQ 14. 53–72.Google Scholar

  • Harris, C. R. S. 1973. The Heart and Vascular System in Ancient Greek Medicine. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Hett, W. S. 1936. Aristotle. On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, on Breath. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • King, R. A. H. 2009. Aristotle and Plotinus on Memory. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar

  • Labarrière, J.-L. 2000. “Sentir le temps, regarder un tableau. Aristote et les images de la mémoire.” In Constructions du temps dans le monde grec ancien, edited by C. Darbo-Peschanski, 269–283. Paris: CNRS Editions.Google Scholar

  • Labarrière, J.-L. 2002. “Phantasia, phantasma, et phainetai dans le traité Des Rêves.” RPhA 20. 89–107.Google Scholar

  • Lloyd, G. E. R. 1978. “The Empirical Basis of the Physiology of the Parva Naturalia.” In Aristotle on the Mind and Senses, edited by G.E.R. Lloyd and G.E.L. Owen, 215–240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Manuli, P., and M. Vegetti. 1977. Cuore, sangue, e cervello: Biologia e antropologia nel pensiero antico. Milan: Episteme.Google Scholar

  • Maquet, P. 2001. “The Role of Sleep in Learning and Memory.” Science 294 (5544): 1048–1052.CrossrefPubMedGoogle Scholar

  • Marelli, C. 1979–80. “Il sonno tra biologia e medicina in Grecia antica.” Bollettino dell’Istituto di Filologia Greca 5. 122–137.Google Scholar

  • Modrak, D. K. W. 1986. “Φαντασία Reconsidered.” AGPh 68. 47–69.Google Scholar

  • Modrak, D. K. W. 1987. Aristotle: The Power of Perception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

  • Morel, P.-M. 2006a. ‘Common to Soul and Body’ in the Parva Naturalia.” In Common to Body and Soul. Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behaviour in Greco-Roman Antiquity, edited by R.A.H. King, 121–139. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar

  • Morel, P.-M. 2006b. “Mémoire et charactère. Aristote et l’histoire personelle.” In Mémoire et souvenir. Six études sur Platon, Aristote, Hegel, et Husserl, edited by A. Brancacci and G. Gigliotti, Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar

  • Moss, J. D. 2012. Aristotle on the Apparent Good: Perception, Phantasia, Thought, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Neuhäuser, J. 1878. Aristoteles’ Lehre von dem sinnlichen Erkenntnissvermögen und seinen Organen. Leipzig: Verlag von Erich Koschny.Google Scholar

  • Nussbaum, M. C. 1978. Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium; Text with Translation, Commentary, and Interpretive Essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

  • Peck, A. L. 1942. Aristotle. Generation of Animals, with an English Translation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Ross, W. D. 1961. Aristotelis De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Segev, M. 2012. “The Teleological Significance of Dreaming in Aristotle.” OSAP 43. 107–141.Google Scholar

  • Shields, C. 1993. “Some Recent Approaches to Aristotle’s De Anima.” In Aristotle De Anima, Books II and III (With Passages from Book I), edited by D.W. Hamlyn, 157–181. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Siegel, J. M. 2001. “The REM Sleep-Memory Consolidation Hypothesis.” Science 294 (5544): 1058–1063.CrossrefPubMedGoogle Scholar

  • Sisko, J. 1996. “Material Alteration and Cognitive Activity in Aristotle’s De Anima.” Phronesis 41 (2): 138–157.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Sisko, J. 1997. “Space, Time and Phantasms in Aristotle, De Memoria 2, 452b7-25.” CQ 47. 167–175.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Solmsen, F. 1961. “Greek Philosophy and the Discovery of the Nerves.” MH 18. 150–197.Google Scholar

  • Sorabji, R. 2006. Aristotle on Memory, 2nd ed. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar

  • Tracy, T. 1969. Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle. The Hague: Mouton & Co.Google Scholar

  • Tracy, T. 1989. “Heart and Soul in Aristotle.” In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, Vol. 2, edited by J. Anton and A. Preus, 321–339. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar

  • Verbeke, G. 1978. “Doctrine du pneuma et entelechisme chez Aristote.” In Aristotle on the Mind and Senses, edited by G.E.R. Lloyd and G.E.L. Owen, 191–214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Watson, G. 1982. “Φαντασία in Aristotle, De Anima 3.3.” CQ 32. 100–113.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Webb, P. 1982. “Bodily Structure and Psychic Faculties in Aristotle’s Theory of Perception.” Hermes 110. 25–50.Google Scholar

  • Wedin, M. V. 1988. Mind and Imagination in Aristotle. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar

  • Wiesner, J. 1978. “The Unity of the Treatise De Somno and the Physiological Explanation of Sleep in Aristotle.” In Aristotle on the Mind and Senses, edited by G.E.R. Lloyd and G.E.L. Owen, 241–280. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Wijsenbeek-Wijler, H. 1978. Aristotle’s Concept of Soul, Sleep and Dreams. Amsterdam: Hakkert.Google Scholar

  • Zierlein, S. 2005. “Aristoteles’ anatomische Vorstellung vom menschlichen Herzen.” Antike Naturwissenschaft und ihre Rezeption 15. 43–71.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2018-10-16


Citation Information: Apeiron, ISSN (Online) 2156-7093, ISSN (Print) 0003-6390, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0015.

Export Citation

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter Inc., Boston/Berlin.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in