Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Apeiron

A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science

Ed. by Wildberg, Christian / Morison, Benjamin

Online
ISSN
2156-7093
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Ahead of print

Issues

Every Man a Legislator: Aristotle on Political Wisdom

Dhananjay Jagannathan
Published Online: 2019-03-06 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0034

Abstract

I argue that Aristotle’s unmodern conception of politics can only be understood by first understanding his distinctive picture of human agency and the excellence of political wisdom. I therefore undertake to consider three related puzzles: (1) why at the outset of the Nicomachean Ethics [NE] is the human good said to be the same for a city and for an individual, such that the NE’s inquiry is political? (2) why later on in the NE is political wisdom said to be the same state of soul as practical wisdom? (3) why in the Politics does Aristotle identify practical wisdom as the peculiar excellence of rulers when deliberation was said to be the common work of all citizens insofar as they are genuinely citizens? While these puzzles have individually received treatment in the literature, they have seldom been treated together. Taken independently, the passages in question can seem to express a more familiar conception of politics. In particular, each of the sameness claims made in (1) and (2) has too easily been assimilated to a more modern conception of the relation of ethics to politics and thereby domesticated. As I hope to show, in (1) Aristotle is not simply asserting that the human good in a city supervenes on the good as achieved by its inhabitants (since this by itself, while true, would fall short of establishing the political character of his inquiry in the NE); and in (2) he is not claiming only that political wisdom is a species of practical wisdom, but is rather asserting a more thoroughgoing identity between various types of deliberative excellence that are conventionally distinguished and assigned different names. Working through these passages will provide a sufficient basis for tackling (3), the question about the respective excellences of rulers and citizens. I will show that, despite his restriction of the exercise of practical wisdom to rulers, Aristotle imagines that non-ruling citizens will also exercise their political agency and thereby require a distinct rational excellence. More precisely, for Aristotle, there are two forms of political agency, deliberation on behalf of one’s community, which is perfected by practical-political wisdom, and the comprehension (sunesis) exercised by citizens on the basis of the view of life preserved by their character-virtues. Understood this way, the division of labor between rulers and citizens does not generate two spheres of activity, political and private, which could have unrelated excellences or concern distinct goods.

Keywords: Aristotle; politics; individualism; totalitarianism; practical wisdom

Bibliography

  • Allan, D.J.. 1965. “Individual and State in Aristotle’s Ethics and Politics.” La Politique d’Aristote, Entretiens sur l’antiquité classique 11: 53–96.Google Scholar

  • Aquinas, St Thomas. 1969. Sententia Libri Ethicorum. Commissio Leonina. Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae.Google Scholar

  • Barnes, Jonathan. 1990. “Aristotle and Political Liberty.” In Aristoteles’ Politik: Symposium Aristotelicum XI, edited by Günther Patzig, Göttingen: Van der Hoeck u. Ruprecht, 249–63.Google Scholar

  • Bodéüs, Richard. 1993. The Political Dimensions of Aristotle’s Ethics, trans J.E. Garrett. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar

  • Bronstein, David. 2016. Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Bywater, Ingram ed. 1894. Aristotelis Ethica Nicomachea. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Cooper, John. 1990/1999. “Political Animals and Civic Friendship.” In Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory, 356–77. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

  • Cooper, John. 2010. “Political Community and the Highest Good.” In Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, edited by J.G. Lennox and R. Bolton, 212–64. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Drefcinski, Shane. 2006. “A Different Solution to an Alleged Contradiction in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 30: 201–10.Google Scholar

  • Ebert, Theodor. 1995. “Phronesis – Anmerkungen zu einem Begriff der Aristotelischen Ethik.” In Aristoteles. Die Nikomachische Ethik, edited by O. Höffe, 165–85. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar

  • Frede, Dorothea. 2005. “Citizenship in Aristotle’s Politics.” In Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Essays, edited by R. Kraut and S. Skultety, 167–84. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar

  • Garsten, Bryan. 2013. “Deliberating and Acting Together.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, edited by Marguerite Deslauriers and Pierre Destrée, New York: Cambridge University Press, 324–49.Google Scholar

  • Irwin, Terence. 1988. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Johnson, Curtis. 1984. “Who Is Aristotle’s Citizen?.” Phronesis 29(1): 73–90.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kamtekar, Rachana. 2014. “The Relationship between Aristotle’s Ethical and Political Discourses (NE X 9).” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, edited by R. Polansky, 370–82. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Katz, Emily. 2017. “Ontological Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.” Phronesis 62(1): 26–68.CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Lautner, Péter. 2013. “Political φρόνησις.” The Politics of Aristotle: Reconstructions and Interpretations, Hungarian Philosophical Review 57(4): 24–33.Google Scholar

  • Miller, Fred, Jr. 1997. Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle’s Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Morrison, Donald. 2013. “The Common Good.” In The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, edited by Marguerite Deslauriers and Pierre Destrée, New York: Cambridge University Press, 176–98.Google Scholar

  • Mulgan, Richard. 2000. “Was Aristotle an “Aristotelian Social Democrat”?.” Ethics 111(1): 79–101.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1988. “Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: 145–84.Google Scholar

  • Peramatzis, Michael. 2011. Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Popper, Karl. 1945. The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

  • Rasmussen, Douglas, and Douglas J. Den Uyl. 1991. Liberty and Nature: An Aristotelian Defense of Liberal Order. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court.Google Scholar

  • Riesbeck, David. 2016. Aristotle on Political Community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Roberts, Jean. 2009. “Excellence of the Citizen and the Individual.” In A Companion to Aristotle, edited by G. Anagnostopoulos, 555–65. Chichester/Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Rosler, Andrés. 2005. Political Authority and Obligation in Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Ross, W.D. ed. 1957. Aristotelis Politica. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Schofield, Malcolm. 2006. “Aristotle’s Political Ethics.” In The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, edited by R. Kraut, 305–22. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Striker, Gisela. 2006. “Aristotle’s Ethics as Political Science.” In The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics, edited by Burkhard Reis, 127–41. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Surprenant, Chris. 2012. “Politics and Practical Wisdom: Rethinking Aristotle’s Account of Phronesis.” Topoi 31(2): 221–27.CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Trott, Adriel. 2014. Aristotle on the Nature of Community. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • White, Stephen A. n.d. “Aristotle on Good Citizenship.” Unpublished ms.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2019-03-06


Citation Information: Apeiron, ISSN (Online) 2156-7093, ISSN (Print) 0003-6390, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0034.

Export Citation

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter Inc., Boston/Berlin.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in