Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Apeiron

A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science

Ed. by Wildberg, Christian / Morison, Benjamin

Online
ISSN
2156-7093
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Ahead of print

Issues

The One over Many Principle of Republic 596a

José Edgar González-VarelaORCID iD: https://orcid.org/0000-0003-1491-1844
Published Online: 2019-06-08 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0086

Abstract

Republic 596a introduces a One over Many principle that has traditionally been considered as an argument for the existence of Forms, according to which, one Form should be posited for each like-named plurality. This interpretation was challenged by (Smith, J. A. 1917. “General Relative Clauses in Greek.” Classical Review 31: 69–71.), who interpreted it rather as a statement that each Form is unique and correlated to a plurality of things that have the same name as it. (Sedley, D. 2013. “Plato and the One-over-Many Principle”, in Chiaradonna & Galluzzo 2013, 113–37.) has offered a forceful defence of Smith’s interpretation. I argue that Sedley’s defence fails and that the traditional interpretation should be preferred.

Keywords: eponymy; forms; plurality; uniqueness; universals

References

  • Adam, J.,ed. 1902. The Republic of Plato, vol. 2 . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Ademollo, F. 2013. “Plato’s Conception of the Forms: Some Remarks.” in Chiaradonna & Galluzzo 2013, 41–85.Google Scholar

  • Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Armstrong, D. 1978. Universals and Scientific Realism, vol. 1: Nominalism and Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Bornemann, E., and E. Risch. 1978. Griechische Grammatik. Frankfurt: Verlag Moritz Diesterweg.Google Scholar

  • Burnyeat, M. F. 1999. “Utopia and Fantasy: The Practicability of Plato’s Ideally Just City.” In Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul, edited by G. Fine, 297–308. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Burnyeat, M. F. 2000. “Plato on Why Mathematics Is Good for the Soul.” In Mathematics and Necessity, edited by T. Smiley, 1–81. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Chiaradonna, R., and G. Galluzzo. 2013. Universals in Ancient Philosophy. Pisa: Edizione Della Normale.Google Scholar

  • Fine, G. 1980. “The One over Many.” Philosophical Review 89: 197–224.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Fine, G. 1993. On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Theory of Forms. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Forcignanò, F. 2014. “Il Problema Delle Idee Di Artefatto in Platone.” Méthexis 27: 61–93.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • González-Varela, J. E. 2018. “The Razor Argument of Metaphysics A.9.” Phronesis 63: 408–48.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Gosling, J. 1960. “Republic Book V: τὰ πολλὰ καλά, Etc.” Phronesis 5: 116–28.Google Scholar

  • Griswold, C. 1981. “The Ideas and the Criticism of Poetry in Plato’s Republic, Book 10.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 19: 135–50.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Harte, V. 2008. “Plato’s Metaphysics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Plato, edited by G. Fine, 191–216. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Mair, A. W. 1918. “General Relative Clauses in Greek.” Classical Review 32: 169–70.Google Scholar

  • Marmodoro, A. 2008. “Is Being One Only One? The Uniqueness of Platonic Forms.” Apeiron 41: 211–28.Google Scholar

  • Nehamas, A. 1999. “Plato on Imitation and Poetry in Republic X.” In Virtues of Authenticity, 251–78. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

  • Parry, R. 1985. “The Uniqueness Proof for Forms in Republic 10.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 23: 133–50.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Patterson, R. 1985. Image and Reality in Plato’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar

  • Reeve, C. D. C., (tr.) 2004. Plato: Republic. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar

  • Robinson, R. 1953. Plato’s Earlier Dialectic, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Scott, D. 2015. Levels of Argument. A Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sedley, D. 2013. “Plato and the One-over-Many Principle.” in Chiaradonna & Galluzzo 2013, 113–37.Google Scholar

  • Sharma, R. 2006. “On Republic 596a.” Apeiron 39: 27–32.Google Scholar

  • Smith, J. A. 1917. “General Relative Clauses in Greek.” Classical Review 31: 69–71.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Smyth, H. W. 1920. A Greek Grammar. New York: American Book Company.Google Scholar

  • Sonnenschein, E. 1918. “The Indicative in Relative Clauses.” Classical Review 32: 68–69.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Vegetti, M.,ed. 2007. Platone: La Repubblica, vol. VII. Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2019-06-08


Funder Name: This work was supported by the PAPIIT DGAPA-UNAM, (Grant Number: IN403819)


Citation Information: Apeiron, ISSN (Online) 2156-7093, ISSN (Print) 0003-6390, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0086.

Export Citation

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter Inc., Boston/Berlin.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in