Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109(2), 287–337.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fox-Piven, F. (2006). Challenging authority. New York: Rowan and Littelfield.Google Scholar
Fox-Piven, F., & Cloward, R. (1979). Poor people’s movements. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Geras, N.. (1985). The controversy about Marx and justice. New Left Review 150, 47–85.Google Scholar
Jenkins, D. (2015). An ethos for (In)justice. Social Theory and Practice, 41(2), 185–206.Google Scholar
Joseph Rowntree Foundation, Monitoring Poverty and Social Inclusion 2014. Retrieved from: http://www.jrf.org.uk/sites/files/jrf/MPSE-2014-FULL.pdf
Marable, M. (2006). Living Black History. New York: Basic Civitas Books.Google Scholar
Marx, K. (1977). The critique of the Gotha program. In McLellan, D. (Ed.), Karl Mark: Selected writings (pp. 610–616). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McAlevey, J. (2014). Raising expectations (and raising hell). London: Verso Books.Google Scholar
Pateman, C. (2003). Freedom and democratization: Why basic income is to be preferred to basic capital. In K. Dowding, et al. (Eds.), Ethics of stakeholding (pp. 130–148). Basingstoke: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Pateman, C. (2004). Democratising citizenship: Some advantages of a basic income. Politics and Society, 32(1), 89–105.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (1996). Freedom as anti-power. Ethics, 106(3), 576–604.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. (2007). A republican right to basic income. Basic Income Studies, 2(2), 1–8.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Roemer, J. (1998). Equality of opportunity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Standing, G. (2011). The precariat: The new dangerous class. London: Bloomsbury Publishing.Google Scholar
Tucker, R. (1969). The Marxian revolutionary idea. New York: Norton Publishers.Google Scholar
Tully, J. (2000). Struggles over recognition and distribution. Constellations, 7(4), 469–482.Google Scholar
Tyson, T. B. (2004). Blood done sign my name. New York: Random Press.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, P. (1995). Real freedom for all. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, P. (1997). Reciprocity and the Justification of an Unconditional Basic Income. Reply to Stuart White. Political Studies, 45(2), 327–330.Crossref
Vanderborght, Y. (2006). Why trade unions oppose basic income. Basic Income Studies, 1(1), 1–20.Google Scholar
Walzer, M. (1970). Obligations. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
White, S. (1996). Needs, labour, and Marx’s conception of justice. Political Studies, 44(1), 88–101.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
White, S. (1997). Liberal Equality, Exploitation and the Case for an Unconditional Basic Income. Political Studies, 45(2), 312–326.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
White, S. (2003). The civic minimum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Widerquist, K. (2013). Independence, propertylessness, and basic income: A theory of freedom as the power to say no. London: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Wolff, J. (1998). Fairness, respect, and the egalitarian ethos. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 27(2), 97–122.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Wood, A. (1972). The Marxian critique of justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(3), 244–282.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. (2001). Activist challenges to deliberative democracy. Political Theory, 29(5), 670–690.CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Young, I. M. (2011). Responsibility for justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Comments (0)