Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie

Zweimonatsschrift der internationalen philosophischen Forschung

Ed. by Demmerling, Christoph / Esser, Andrea Marlen / Krüger, Hans-Peter / Menke, Christoph


CiteScore 2018: 0.06

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2018: 0.139
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2018: 0.234

Online
ISSN
2192-1482
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Volume 66, Issue 1

Issues

Geschichtsphilosophie und Philosophiegeschichte

Einsichten und Paradoxien

Prof. Dr. Wilhelm Schmidt-Biggemann
Published Online: 2018-03-20 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/dzph-2018-0002

Abstract

The essay – an elaborated version of my academic farewell speech [Abschiedsvorlesung] – discusses three theses: 1. Histories and history as well as history of philosophy and philosophy of history can only be staged as narratives. “True” stories enact the past and deliver schemes for anticipating the future; insofar history and future constitute the semantics of the present. 2. “Systematic” philosophy analyses the temporal narratives which store the historical experiences and eliminates their temporality in a process of transforming narratives into arguments. The most important step in this transformation consists in isolating the key notions of the narratives and in arranging these key notions in a “timeless” systematic order. 3. History of philosophy and philosophy of history restage, however, the temporal narrative, which systematic philosophy wants to eliminate from philosophy. This operation produces an unsolvable paradox where the claim of timeless truth and that of unescapable temporality are both valid. It throws up questions such as: how can it be possible for philosophical truths to lose their credit? Do timeless truths exist, and if so what do they mean? Do these paradoxes lead to schadenfreude on the part of the historian of philosophy, who knew it all along, or should one see these unsolvable complexities as a chance to enjoy the richness of possibilities which history unfolds? The essay chooses the second alternative.

Keywords: narrative; philosophy of history; history of philosophy; systematic philosophy; temporality; paradox

Literatur

  • Brucker, J. (1975), Dissertatio praeliminaris de natura, constitutione, usu mediisque historiae philosophicae, in: ders., Historia Critica Philosophiae 1 [Leipzig 1742], Hildesheim, 3–45.Google Scholar

  • Fichte, J. G. (1794), Wissenschaftslehre, Weimar.Google Scholar

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1970), Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte (= Werke 12), Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar

  • Henrich, D. (1967), Fichtes ursprüngliche Einsicht, Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar

  • Husserl, E. (1922), Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, 2. Aufl., Halle (Saale).Google Scholar

  • Koselleck, R. (1979), Erfahrungsraum und Erwartungshorizont, in: ders., Vergangene Zukunft. Zur Semantik geschichtlicher Zeiten, Frankfurt am Main, 349–374.Google Scholar

  • Löwith, K. (1953), Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen [Meaning in History. The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of History, 1949], Stuttgart.Google Scholar

  • Plotin (1878), Die Enneaden, Berlin.Google Scholar

  • Ricœur, P. (1983–1985), Temps et récit, 3 Bde., Paris.Google Scholar

  • Ryle, G. (1945/1946), Knowing How and Knowing That, in: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 46, 1–16.Google Scholar

  • Schmidt-Biggemann, W. (1998), Jacob Bruckers philosophiegeschichtliches Konzept, in: ders. u. Stammen, T. (Hg.), Jacob Brucker (1696–1770), Berlin, 113–134.Google Scholar

  • Schmidt-Biggemann, W. (2007), Nachspiel: Ereignis, Zeit, Erzählung. Eine geschichtsphilosophische Betrachtung, in: ders., Apokalypse und Philologie. Wissensgeschichten und Weltentwürfe der Frühen Neuzeit, Göttingen, 357–379.Google Scholar

  • Schmidt-Biggemann, W. (2014), Geschichte Wissen. Eine Philosophie der Kontingenz im Anschluss an Schelling, Stuttgart.Google Scholar

  • Specht, R. (1972), Innovation und Folgelast. Beispiele aus der neueren Philosophie- und Wissenschaftsgeschichte, Stuttgart.Google Scholar

  • Strawson, P. F. (1995), Einzelding und logisches Subjekt (Individuals) [1959], Stuttgart.Google Scholar

  • Tugendhat, E. (1958), Ti kata tinos, München.Google Scholar

  • Strub, C. (1995), System 7, in: Gründer, K. (Hg.), Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie 9, Basel, Spp. 839–846.Google Scholar

  • Voltaire (1765), Philosophie de l’histoire, Amsterdam.Google Scholar

  • White, H. V. (1973), Metahistory. The Historical Imagination of Nineteenth-century Europe, Baltimore, Md.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2018-03-20

Published in Print: 2018-03-26


Citation Information: Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Volume 66, Issue 1, Pages 2–24, ISSN (Online) 2192-1482, ISSN (Print) 0012-1045, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/dzph-2018-0002.

Export Citation

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in