Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie

Zweimonatsschrift der internationalen philosophischen Forschung

Ed. by Demmerling, Christoph / Esser, Andrea Marlen / Krüger, Hans-Peter / Menke, Christoph


CiteScore 2018: 0.06

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2018: 0.139
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2018: 0.234

Online
ISSN
2192-1482
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Volume 66, Issue 2

Issues

Tentative Sprechakte

Zur erstaunlichen Entfaltbarkeit von Hintergründen beim Formulieren

Donata Schoeller
Published Online: 2018-04-20 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/dzph-2018-0015

Abstract

This paper introduces speech acts that I denote as tentative, which means they do not make sense as single propositions. The meaning they make depends on the attempt to formulate something which seems difficult to put in words. There is no finished intention, feeling or idea to be represented; neither can one construct whatever one wants to say. Tentative speech acts make sense by literally speaking into a felt complexity, as Eugene Gendlin demonstrates. What needs to be understood in regards to these speech acts is a development of meaning occurring during the formulation and not the ontological status of inner entities. A happy outcome of tentative speech acts is a clarification of some aspect of a situation, problem, puzzlement or vague idea, at times involving complex implicit contexts, backgrounds and what Dilthey termed “Lebenszusammenhänge”. In order to speak of these kinds of complex points of reference, John Dewey introduced the term of the „quality of a situation“ and Eugene Gendlin the term „felt sense“. The paper explores ways to approach these speech acts and to consider their philosophical relevance.

Keywords: background; situations; context; language games; experiential response; clarifying process; complex experience; interaction; meaning

Literatur

  • Adorno, T. (1975), Negative Dialektik, Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar

  • Austin, J. (1962), How to Do Things with Words: The William James Lectures Delivered at Harvard University in 1955, Oxford.Google Scholar

  • Barwise, J. (1988), On the Circumstantial Relation between Meaning and Content, in: Eco, U., Santambrogio, M., u. Violi, P. (Hg.), Meaning and Mental Representation, Bloomington, Ind., 23–39.Google Scholar

  • Damasio, A. (1994), Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain, New York.Google Scholar

  • Damasio, A. (1999), Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, New York.Google Scholar

  • Dewey, J. (1917), The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy, in: Dewey, J., Moore, W., Brown, H., Mead, G., Bode, H., Stuart, H., Tufts, J., u. Kallen, H. (Hg.), Creative Intelligence: Essays in the Pragmatic Attitude, New York, 3–69.Google Scholar

  • Dewey, J. (1934), Art as Experience, London.Google Scholar

  • Dewey, J. (1984), Qualitative Thought, in: ders., The Later Works 5 (1925–1953), hg. v. Boydston, J., Carbondale, Ill., 243–262.Google Scholar

  • Dilthey, W. (1982), Leben und Erkennen. Ein Entwurf zur erkenntnistheoretischen Logik und Kategorienlehre [ca. 1892/93], in: ders., Gesammelte Schriften 19, hg. v. Johach, H., u. Rodi, F., Göttingen, 333–388.Google Scholar

  • Dürr, H. (1981), Über Heisenberg zum 80. Geburtstag [unveröff. Ms.].Google Scholar

  • Frankfurt, H. (2006), Taking Ourselves Seriously and Getting It Right, Stanford, Calif.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1966), The Discovery of Felt Meaning, in: McDonald, J., u. Leeper, R. (Hg.), Language and Meaning. Papers from the ASCD Conference, The Curriculum Research Institute (21.–24.11.1964 u. 20.–23.3.1965), Washington, D. C., 45–62.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1968), The Experiential Response, in: Hammer, E. (Hg.), Use of Interpretation in Treatment, New York, 208–227.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1970), The Significance of Felt Meaning, in: Cormier, R., Chinn, E., u. Lineback, R. (Hg.), Encounter. An Introduction to Philosophy, Glenview, Ill., 561–566.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1973), Experiential Phenomenology, in: Natanson, M. (Hg.), Phenomenology and the Social Sciences 1, Evanston, Ill., 281–319.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1991), Thinking Beyond Patterns. Body, Language and Situations, in: Ouden, B., u. Moen, M. (Hg.), The Presence of Feeling in Thought, New York, 25–151.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1992a), Celebrations and Problems of Humanistic Psychology, in: Humanistic Psychologist 20.2–3, 447–460.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1992b), The Wider Role of Bodily Sense in Thought and Language, in: Sheets- Johnstone, M. (Hg.), Giving the Body Its Due, Albany, N. Y., 192–207.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1997), Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning. A Philosophical and Psychological Approach to the Subjective, Evanston, Ill.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (1999), Implicit Entry and Focusing, in: The Humanistic Psychologist 27.1, 80–88.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (2001), Introduction to TAE, in: The Folio 19, 1–11.Google Scholar

  • Gendlin, E. (2004), The new phenomenology of carrying forward, in: Continental Philosophy Review 37.1, 127–151.Google Scholar

  • Husserl, E. (1995), Cartesianische Meditationen. Eine Einleitung in die Phänomenologie [1. Aufl. 1950], 3. durchges. Aufl., Hamburg.Google Scholar

  • James, W. (1950), The Principles of Psychology 1 [1890], New York.Google Scholar

  • Jung, M. (1996), Wilhelm Dilthey zur Einführung, Hamburg.Google Scholar

  • Kant, I. (1989), Prolegomena zu einer jeden zukünftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können [1783], Stuttgart.Google Scholar

  • Kant, I. (1992), Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in: ders., Werkausgabe 3–4, hg. v. Weischedel, W., 12. Aufl., Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar

  • Kleist, H. (2012), Über die allmähliche Verfertigung der Gedanken beim Reden, in: ders., Der Zweikampf. Die heilige Cäcilie. Sämtliche Anekdoten. Über das Marionettentheater und andere Prosa, Stuttgart, 88–94.Google Scholar

  • Koopman, C. (2009), Pragmatism as Transition, New York.Google Scholar

  • Mann, T. (1926), Der Zauberberg, Berlin.Google Scholar

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1966), Phänomenologie der Wahrnehmung, Berlin.Google Scholar

  • Montaigne, M. (2014), Vom Dünkel, in: Essais, ausgew. u. eingel. v. Franz, A., Stuttgart, 239–259.Google Scholar

  • Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere, New York.Google Scholar

  • Noë, A. (2006), Action in Perception, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar

  • Noë, A. (2012), Varieties of Presence, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar

  • Petitmengin, C. (2007), Toward the Source of Thoughts. The Gestural and Transmodal Dimension of Lived Experience, in: Journal of Consciousness Studies 14.3, 54–82.Google Scholar

  • Petitmengin, C., u. Bitbol, M. (2009), The Validity of First-Person Descriptions as Authenticity and Coherence, in: Journal of Consciousness Studies 16.11–12, 363–404.Google Scholar

  • Petitmengin, C. (2011), Describing the Experience of Describing. The Blind Spot of Introspection, in: Journal of Consciousness Studies 18.1, 44–62.Google Scholar

  • Petitmengin, C., u. Lachaux, J. (2013), Microcognitive Science. Bridging Experiential and Neuronal Microdynamics, in: Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, .CrossrefPubMedWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2008), Feelings of Being. Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality, Oxford.Google Scholar

  • Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton, N. J.Google Scholar

  • Rorty, R. (1989), Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar

  • Schmitz, H. (2007), Der unerschöpfliche Gegenstand. Grundzüge der Philosophie, 3. Aufl., Bonn.Google Scholar

  • Schoeller, D. (2018) (i. E.), Close Talking. Von Hintergründen sprechen.Google Scholar

  • Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality. An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar

  • Stuart, S. (2010), Enkinaesthesia, Biosemiotics and the Ethiosphere, in: Cowley, S., Major, J., Steffensen, S., u. Dinis, A. (Hg.), Signifying Bodies. Biosemiosis, Interaction and Health, Braga, 305–330.Google Scholar

  • Stuart, S. (2011), Enkinaesthesia. The Fundamental Challenge for Machine Consciousness, in: International Journal of Machine Consciousness 3.1, 145–162.Google Scholar

  • Williams, M. (1997), The Implicit Intricacy of Mind and Situation, in: Levin, Language Beyond Postmodernism: Saying and Thinking in Gendlin’s Philosophy, Evanston, Ill., 120–147.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2018-04-20

Published in Print: 2018-04-02


Citation Information: Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Volume 66, Issue 2, Pages 183–201, ISSN (Online) 2192-1482, ISSN (Print) 0012-1045, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/dzph-2018-0015.

Export Citation

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in