Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Journal of Literary Theory

Ed. by Jannidis, Fotis / Kindt, Tom / Köppe, Tilmann / Winko, Simone

Online
ISSN
1862-8990
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Deduktive Schlüsse in der literaturwissenschaftlichen Praxis

Stefan Descher
Published Online: 2019-09-04 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0005

Abstract

It is sometimes suggested that deductive reasoning has no place in literary studies, particularly when it comes to the justification of literary interpretations. The thesis is that deductive arguments (almost) never occur and deductive reasoning plays no or at most a marginal role in the actual practice of interpretation. In this essay I will argue that this thesis is false. Using counterexamples, it can be shown that deductive arguments are de facto used in the practice of literary interpretation. Although only an exemplary and not comprehensive investigation of argumentative practices in literary studies can be made here, it can also be made plausible that deductive arguments are not exceptions, but a normal, regularly encountered and legitimate phenomenon of this practice. Furthermore, it can be shown that the thesis criticized here is based on a too narrow understanding of deductive reasoning. Finally, I will argue that (from a methodological point of view) it would be an unnecessary restriction to exclude deductions from our methodological toolbox: to abandon deductive reasoning from the practice of interpretation would be tantamount to renouncing a useful method of justifying (and refuting) interpretive hypotheses. Therefore, a fundamental methodological scepticism about deductive reasoning is unfounded.

The essay is structured as follows: First, I will present a current example of how the sceptical attitude towards deductions in literary studies is motivated (Section 1). I will show that the concept of deduction underlying this scepticism is usually based on the assumption that deductive arguments contain ›general rules‹ or ›law-like assertions‹ in their premises. Second, I will confront the concept of deduction assumed there with the understanding of deductive arguments as it is usually assumed in logic (Section 2). It will become apparent that a conception of deductive arguments based on general rules or law-like assertions is (though not false) too narrow. After a short caveat concerning the reconstruction of ›real‹ arguments in general (Section 3), I will present some examples of deductive arguments in interpretations of literary texts (Section 4). These arguments have the logical form of arguments from modus ponens, modus tollens and disjunctive syllogism. The examples not only show that deductive reasoning actually occurs in the practice of literary interpretation, but also make it plausible that deductive arguments are an unproblematic and legitimate method of justifying and/or refuting interpretations. After considering what causes may have led to the dissemination of the thesis that deductions do not occur in practice (Section 5), I conclude with a plea to accept deductive arguments as a legitimate tool of justification among many others (Section 6).

Schlagworte: Begründungsmethoden; Deduktion; Interpretationspraxis

Literatur

  • Beckermann, Ansgar, Einführung in die Logik, Berlin/Boston 42014.Google Scholar

  • Brun, Georg/Gertrude Hirsch Hadorn, Textanalyse in den Wissenschaften. Inhalte und Argumente analysieren und verstehen, Zürich 2009.Google Scholar

  • Descher, Stefan/Thomas Petraschka, Die Explizierung des Impliziten. Zu einem Grundlagenproblem der Untersuchung literaturwissenschaftlicher Interpretationspraktiken am Beispiel von Droste-Hülshoffs »Der Knabe im Moor«, Scientia Poetica 22 (2018), 180–207.Google Scholar

  • Douven, Igor, Abduction, in: Edward N. Zalta (Hg.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/abduction.

  • Fricke, Harald/Rüdiger Zymner, Einübung in die Literaturwissenschaft, Paderborn u. a. 21993.Google Scholar

  • Harzer, Friedmann, Literarische Texte interpretieren. Lyrik – Prosa – Drama, Stuttgart 2017.Google Scholar

  • Jäger, Georg, Liebe als Medienrealität. Eine semiotische Problemexplikation, in: Siegfried J. Schmidt (Hg.), Literaturwissenschaft und Systemtheorie. Positionen, Kontroversen, Perspektiven, Opladen 1993, 44–65.Google Scholar

  • Mecklenburg, Norbert, Der Fall »Judenbuche«. Revision eines Fehlurteils, Bielefeld 2008.Google Scholar

  • Metz, Christian, Diffraktive Poetologie. Monika Rincks Poetik des Sprungs. Eine Lektüre, Zeitschrift für Germanistik 28:2 (2018), 247–260.Google Scholar

  • Priest, Graham, Logic. A Very Short Introduction, Oxford 2000.Google Scholar

  • Salmon, Wesley, Logic, Englewood Cliffs, NJ 21973.Google Scholar

  • Schurz, Gerhard, Einführung in die Wissenschaftstheorie, Darmstadt 42014.Google Scholar

  • Van Eemeren, Frans H./Rob Grootendorst, A Systematic Theory of Argumentation. The Pragma-Dialectical Approach, Cambridge u. a. 2004.Google Scholar

  • Viehoff, Reinhold, Glossar, in: Helmut Kreuzer/R.V. (Hg.), Literaturwissenschaft und empirische Methoden. Eine Einführung in aktuelle Projekte, Göttingen 1981, 369–378.Google Scholar

  • Winko, Simone/Fotis Jannidis, Wissen und Inferenz. Zum Verstehen und Interpretieren literarischer Texte am Beispiel von Hans Magnus Enzensbergers Gedicht Frühschriften, in: Jan Borkowski u. a. (Hg.), Literatur interpretieren. Interdisziplinäre Beiträge zur Theorie und Praxis, Münster 2015, 221–250.Google Scholar

  • Zoglauer, Thomas, Einführung in die formale Logik für Philosophen, Göttingen 22002.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2019-09-04

Published in Print: 2019-09-06


Citation Information: Journal of Literary Theory, Volume 13, Issue 2, Pages 145–160, ISSN (Online) 1862-8990, ISSN (Print) 1862-5290, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0005.

Export Citation

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in