Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Kairos. Journal of Philosophy & Science

3 Issues per year

Open Access
Online
ISSN
1647-659X
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Enactivism, Radical Enactivism and Predictive Processing: What is Radical in Cognitive Science?

Klaus Gärtner
  • Center for Philosophy of Sciences of the University of Lisbon (CFCUL)
  • Email:
/ Robert W. Clowes
  • Nova Institute of Philosophy (IFILNOVA)/Faculty of Social Sciences and Humanities of the Universidade Nova de Lisboa (FCSH)
  • Email:
Published Online: 2017-06-06 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/kjps-2017-0003

Abstract

According to Enactivism, cognition should be understood in terms of a dynamic interaction between an acting organism and its environment. Further, this view holds that organisms do not passively receive information from this environment, they rather selectively create this environment by engaging in interaction with the world. Radical Enactivism adds that basic cognition does so without entertaining representations and hence that representations are not an essential constituent of cognition. Some proponents think that getting rid of representations amounts to a revolutionary alternative to standard views about cognition. To emphasize the impact, they claim that this ‘radicalization’ should be applied to all enactivist friendly views, including, another current and potentially revolutionary approach to cognition: predictive processing. In this paper, we will show that this is not the case. After introducing the problem (section 2), we will argue (section 3) that ‘radicalizing’ predictive processing does not add any value to this approach. After this (section 4), we will analyze whether or not radical Enactivism can count as a revolution within cognitive science at all and conclude that it cannot. Finally, in section 5 we will claim that cognitive science is better off when embracing heterogeneity.

Keywords: Enactivism; Radical enactivism; Predictive processing; Mental representations; Mental content; Conceptual revolution

References

  • Bermúdez, J.L. (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford.Google Scholar

  • Block, N. (1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19–49.Google Scholar

  • Brooks, R. (1995). Intelligence Without Reason. In L. Steels & R. Brooks (Eds.), The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence: Building Embodied, Situated Agents. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar

  • Brooks, R., & Stein, L.A. (1993). Building Brains for Bodies (1439). Retrieved from http://people.csail.mit.edu/brooks/papers/brains.pdf

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, A.J. (1994). Doing without representing. Synthese, 10, 401-431.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2012a). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind 121 (483), 753-771. doi: 10.1093/mind/fzs106.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2012b). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 36(3), 181–253.Google Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2015a). Embodied prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND (7), 1-21. doi: 10.15502/9783958570115.Google Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2015b). Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs 00:0, 1-27. doi:10.1111/nous.12140.Google Scholar

  • Clowes, R.W. (2017). The Ipseity Disturbance Theory of Schizophrenia and Predictive Processing. In I. Hipólito, J. Gonçalves, & J. G. Pereira (Eds.), Schizophrenia and Common Sense: explaining madness and social values. : Springer Mind Brain Studies.Google Scholar

  • Clowes, R.W., & Chrisley, R. (2012). Virtualist Representation. International Journal of Machine Consciousness, 04(02), 503-522.Google Scholar

  • Clowes, R.W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation Redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, Special Issue on Representation(Special Issue: Explaining Representation), 26-47.Google Scholar

  • Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation-hunger reconsidered. Synthese, 191 (15), 3639-3648.Google Scholar

  • Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9-21.Google Scholar

  • Di Paolo, E., & Thompson, E. (2014). The enactive approach. The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition, 68-78.Google Scholar

  • Fletcher, P. & Frith, C. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews: Neuro-science 10, 48–58.Google Scholar

  • Fodor, J. (1981). Representations, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Fresco, N. (2010). Explaining Computation Without Semantics: Keeping it Simple. Minds and Machines 20(2), 165–181. doi:10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 293-301.Google Scholar

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Gładziejewski, P. (2015). Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese 193, 559–582 doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). The intentionality all-stars. Philosophical perspectives, 383-427.Google Scholar

  • Hohwy, J. (2004). Top-down and bottom-up in delusion formation. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11(1), 65-70.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Hohwy, J. (2014). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12062.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A. & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition 108(3), 687–701.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hume, D. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature (Second Edition). Sir Lewis Amherst Selby-Bigge, first baronet & P. H. Nidditch (eds.). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Hutto, D.D. (2011). Enactivism: Why be radical. Sehen und Handeln, 21-44.Google Scholar

  • Hutto, D.D. (2015). REC: Revolution Effected by Clarification. Topoi, 1-15. doi:10.1007/s11245-015-9358-8.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hutto, D.D., Kirchhoff, M. D., & Abrahamson, D. (2015). The enactive roots of STEM: rethinking educational design in mathematics. Educational Psychology Review, 27(3), 371-389.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (Forthcoming). Going Radical. Retrieved from https://www.academia.edu/15763822/Going_Radical?auto=download.

  • Hutto, D.D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521-536.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kriegel, U. (2002). PANIC Theory and the Prospects for a Representationalist Theory of Phenomenal Consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 15, 55-64.Google Scholar

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (1999). Concepts: core readings: Mit Press.Google Scholar

  • Miłkowski M. (2013). A mechanistic account of computational explanation in cognitive science. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Cooperative Minds: Social Interaction and Group Dynamics, Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society, 3050–3055. Available online at: http://csjarchive.cogsci.rpi.edu/Proceedings/2013/papers/0545/paper0545.pdf.

  • Miłkowski, M. (2016a). Function and causal relevance of content. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 94-102.Google Scholar

  • Miłkowski, M. (2016b). Unification Strategies in Cognitive Science. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 48(61), 13-33.Google Scholar

  • O’Regan, J.K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939-973.Google Scholar

  • Piccinini, G. (2006). Computation without Representation. Philosophical Studies 137(2), 205–241. doi:10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Pitt, D. (2013). Mental Representation. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2013 Edition, URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/mental-representation/>.

  • Sacks, O. (2012). Hallucinations: Pan Macmillan.Google Scholar

  • Seth, A.K., Suzuki, K. & Critchley, H.D. (2011). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology 2, 395.Google Scholar

  • Shoemaker, S. (1994): Identity, Cause, and Mind. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Steels, L. (1997). Constructing and Sharing Perceptual Distinctions. Paper presented at the Proceedings of the European Conference on Machine Learning, Prague. Springer Verlag, Berlin.Google Scholar

  • Steels, L., & Belpaeme, T. (2005). Coordinating Perceptually Grounded Categories through Language: A Case Study for Colour. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 469-489.Google Scholar

  • Stich, S. (1983). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. The MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

  • Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Watson, J.B. (1913). Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it. Psychological Review 20, 158-177.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2017-06-06

Published in Print: 2017-04-01


Citation Information: Kairos. Journal of Philosophy & Science, ISSN (Online) 1647-659X, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/kjps-2017-0003.

Export Citation

© 2017 Klaus Gärtner et al., published by De Gruyter Open. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License. BY-NC-ND 3.0

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in