Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Lodz Papers in Pragmatics

Founded by Cap, Piotr

Editor-in-Chief: Chilton, Paul / Kopytowska, Monika


CiteScore 2017: 0.35

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2017: 0.249
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2017: 0.074

Print + Online
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Perspectives on Context and Contextualism

Piotr Stalmaszczyk / Monika Kopytowska
Published Online: 2012-01-05 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/v10016-011-0009-2

Perspectives on Context and Contextualism

  • Annis, David. 1978. A Contextualist Theory of Epistemic Justification. American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 213-229.Google Scholar

  • Austin, John. 1961/1979. Performative utterances. In: Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press (3rd ed.), 233-252.Google Scholar

  • Bianchi, Claudia. 2010. Contextualism. In: Jan-Ola Östman and Jef Verschueren (eds.), Handbook of Pragmatics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 2-22.Google Scholar

  • Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2008. Conversational implicature and the cancellability test. Analysis 68: 156-160.Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Cappelen, Herman and John Hawthorne. 2009. Relativism and Monadic Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Cappelen, Herman and Ernie Lepore. 2005. Insensitive Semantics. A Defense of Semantic Minimalism and Speech Act Pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Conant, James. 1998. Wittgenstein on Meaning and Use. Philosophical Investigations 21(3): 222-250.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • DeRose, Keith, 1999. Contextualism: An Explanation and Defense. In: John Greco and Ernest Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell, 187-205.Google Scholar

  • DeRose, Keith, 2009. The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Dummett, Michael. 1993. Origins of Analytical Philosophy. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar

  • Frege, Gottlob. [1884] 1953/1960. The Foundations of Arithmetic, tr. John L. Austin (2nd ed.). New York: Harper Torchbook.Google Scholar

  • Gauker, Christopher. 2002. Words without Meaning. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Gauker, Christopher. 2008. Against accommodation: Heim, van der Sandt, and the presupposition projection problem. Philosophy of Language 22: 171-205.Google Scholar

  • Grice, Henry P. 1978/1989. Further Notes on Logic and Conversation. In: Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 41-57.Google Scholar

  • Jaszczolt, Katarzyna, M. 2005. Default Semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Jaszczolt, Katarzyna, M. 2010. Post-Gricean pragmatics. In: Louise Cummings (ed.), The Pragmatics Encyclopedia. London: Routledge, 332-334.Google Scholar

  • Levinson, Stephen. C. 2000. Presumptive Meanings: The Conversational Implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Ludlow, Peter. 2005. Contextualism and the New Linguistic Turn in Epistemology. In: Gerhard Preyer and Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy. Knowledge, Meaning and Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 11-50.Google Scholar

  • Ludlow, Peter. 2008. Cheap Contextualism. Philosophical Issues 18, Interdisciplinary Core Philosophy: 104-129.Google Scholar

  • Recanati, François. 1993. Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Recanati, François. 2004. Literal Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Recanati, François. 2005. Literalism and contextualism: Some varieties. In: Gerhard Preyer and Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 171-196.Google Scholar

  • Recanati, François. 2010. Truth-Conditional Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Searle, John. 1979. Expression and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sosa, Ernest and Enrique Villanueva (eds.). 2000. Skepticism. Philosophical Issues 10, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Sperber, Dan and Deirdre Wilson. 1986/1995. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 2002. Common Ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25(5-6): 701-721.Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Travis, Charles. 1975. Saying and Understanding. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Travis, Charles. 1989. The Uses of Sense: Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Travis, Charles. 2006. Thought's Footing: A Theme in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Waismann, Friedrich. 1940. Verifiability. In: Antony Flew (ed.) 1951. Logic and Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Weiner, Matthew. 2006. Are all conversational implicatures cancellable? Analysis 66: 127-130.Google Scholar

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953/1958. Philosophical Investigations. Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe and Rush Rhees (eds.), tr. Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

About the article


Published Online: 2012-01-05

Published in Print: 2011-01-01


Citation Information: Lodz Papers in Pragmatics, Volume 7, Issue 2, Pages 181–187, ISSN (Online) 1898-4436, ISSN (Print) 1895-6106, DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/v10016-011-0009-2.

Export Citation

This content is open access.

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in