Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Lodz Papers in Pragmatics

Founded by Cap, Piotr

Editor-in-Chief: Chilton, Paul / Kopytowska, Monika


CiteScore 2017: 0.35

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2017: 0.249
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2017: 0.074

Online
ISSN
1898-4436
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Contextualism and Disagreement

Wang Qin
Published Online: 2012-01-05 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/v10016-011-0017-2

Contextualism and Disagreement

This paper argues that attributor contextualism is in conflict with ordinary language methodology. Attributor contextualism has at its center the thesis that, the truth-values of knowledge attributions vary with the conversational (speaker) contexts. This thesis entails that if two speakers in similar contexts make conflicting knowledge attributions, at least one of these attributions is false. One important argument for attributor contextualism depends on ordinary language methodology, a methodology that places great trust in ordinary speakers and prevents judging a substantial group of ordinary speakers' simple knowledge attributions false. I argue that there is strong empirical evidence that ordinary speakers do extensively disagree in similar contexts. My conclusion is that one cannot coherently hold the attributor contextualist thesis and use ordinary language methodology, because the lesson we learn from the empirical evidence is that using the methodology would prove the thesis false. Since prominent attributor contextualists explicitly adopt the methodology, and that the methodology is what distinguishes attributor contextualism from its main rival, invariantism, the conflict with the methodology is a problem for attributor contextualism.

Keywords: attributor contextualism; ordinary language; disagreement

  • Chrisman, Matthew. 2007. From epistemic contextualism to epistemic expressivism. Philosophical Studies 135(2): 225-254.Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Cohen, Stewart. 1999. Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 57-89.Google Scholar

  • Cohen, Stewart. 2001. Contextualism defended: Comments on Richard Feldman's skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies 103(1): 87-98.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Cullen, Simon. 2010. Survey-Driven Romanticism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1(3): 275-296.Google Scholar

  • DeRose, Keith. 1995. Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review 104(1): 1-52.CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • DeRose, Keith. 1999. Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In: John Greco and Ernest Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, 187-205.Google Scholar

  • DeRose, Keith. 2008. What's Wrong with Experimental Philosophy. In: Certain Doubts. Retrieved May 24, 2010, from http://el-prod.baylor.edu/certain_doubts/?p=837

  • DeRose, Keith. 2009. The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

  • Haberstroh, Susanne, Daphna Oyserman, Norbert Schwarz, Ulrich Kühnen and Li-Jun Ji. 2002. Is the interdependent self more sensitive to question context than the independent self? Self-construal and the observation of conversational norms. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 38(3): 323-329, doi:10.1006/jesp.2001.1513.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Holbrook, Allyson L., Jon A. Krosnick, David Moore and Roger Tourangeau. 2007. Response order effects in dichotomous categorical questions presented orally: the impact of question and respondent attributes. The Public Opinion Quarterly 71(3): 325-348.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Johnson, Timothy, Patrick Kulesa, Isr Llc, Young I. Cho and Sharon Shavitt. 2005. The relation between culture and response styles: evidence from 19 countries. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 36(2): 264-277, doi:10.1177/0022022104272905.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Krosnick, Jon A. 1999. Survey research. Annual Review of Psychology 50(1): 537-567.CrossrefWeb of SciencePubMedGoogle Scholar

  • Lewis, David. 1996. Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74(4): 549-567.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Weinberg, Jonathan M., Shaun Nichols and Stephen Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29(1-2): 429-460.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Welkenhuysen-Gybels, Jerry, Jaak Billiet and Bart Cambre. 2003. Adjustment for acquiescence in the assessment of the construct equivalence of Likert-type score items. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 34(6): 702-722, doi:10.1177/0022022103257070.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

About the article


Published Online: 2012-01-05

Published in Print: 2011-01-01


Citation Information: Lodz Papers in Pragmatics, Volume 7, Issue 2, Pages 309–322, ISSN (Online) 1898-4436, ISSN (Print) 1895-6106, DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/v10016-011-0017-2.

Export Citation

This content is open access.

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in