Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Moral Philosophy and Politics

Editor-in-Chief: Schefczyk, Michael

Managing Editor: Schmidt-Petri, Christoph

Ed. by Meyer, Lukas Heinrich / Peacock, Mark / Schaber, Peter

2 Issues per year

Online
ISSN
2194-5624
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Indirect Instrumentalism about Political Legitimacy

Matthias Brinkmann
  • Corresponding author
  • Political Philosophy, Policy & Law, University of Virginia, Gibson Hall S495, Charlottesville, VA 22904, USA
  • Email
  • Other articles by this author:
  • De Gruyter OnlineGoogle Scholar
Published Online: 2018-10-27 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/mopp-2018-0024

Abstract

Political instrumentalism claims that the right to rule should be distributed such that justice is promoted best. Building on a distinction made by consequentialists in moral philosophy, I argue that instrumentalists should distinguish two levels of normative thinking about legitimacy, the critical and applied level. An indirect instrumentalism which acknowledges this distinction has significant advantages over simpler forms of instrumentalism that do not.

Keywords: political legitimacy; instrumentalism; justice; consequentialism; indirect moral theories

References

  • Acemoglu, D. and Robinson, J. (2012). Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty (New York: Crown Publishers).Google Scholar

  • Alexander, L. (1985). ‘Pursuing the Good–Indirectly’, Ethics 95 (2): 315–332.Google Scholar

  • Alexander, L. (1991). ‘The Gap’, Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 14: 695–701.Google Scholar

  • Alexander, L. and Sherwin, E. (2001). The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of Law (Durham: Duke University Press).Google Scholar

  • Applbaum, A. (2004). ‘Legitimacy in a Bastard Kingdom’, Center for Public Leadership Working Paper Series, Harvard Kennedy School, http://dspace.mit.edu/handle/1721.1/55927 (accessed on 16th July 2018).

  • Arneson, R. (2003). ‘Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy’, Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (1): 122–132.Google Scholar

  • Bales, E. (1971). ‘Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?’, American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (3): 257–265.Google Scholar

  • Brandt, R.B. (1988). ‘Fairness to Indirect Optimific Theories in Ethics’, Ethics 98 (2): 341–360.Google Scholar

  • Brinkmann, M. (2017). A Rationalist Theory of Legitimacy. D.Phil. thesis, University of Oxford, https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:6efb1b18-d901-40d3-9131-b83a4a10a642 or http://matthiasbrinkmann.de/docs/dphil.pdf (accessed on 10th September 2018).

  • Brinkmann, M. (2018). ‘Coordination Cannot Establish Political Authority’, Ratio Juris 31 (1): 49–69.Google Scholar

  • Buchanan, A. (1999). ‘Rule-Governed Institutions versus Act-Consequentialism: A Rejoinder to Naticchia’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 28 (3): 258–270.Google Scholar

  • Buchanan, A. (2002). ‘Political Legitimacy and Democracy’, Ethics 112 (4): 689–719.Google Scholar

  • Buchanan, A. (2004). Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar

  • Buck, R. (2012). ‘Democratic Legitimacy: The Limits of Instrumentalist Accounts’, Journal of Value Inquiry 46 (2): 223–236.Google Scholar

  • Christman, J. (2002). Social and Political Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction (London: Routledge).Google Scholar

  • Coakley, M. (2011). ‘On the Value of Political Legitimacy’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics 10 (4): 345–369.Google Scholar

  • Crisp, R. (1992). ‘Utilitarianism and the Life of Virtue’, Philosophical Quarterly 42: 139–160.Google Scholar

  • Dworkin, R. (2003). ‘What is Equality? Part 4: Political Equality’, in T. Christiano (ed.), Philosophy and Democracy: An Anthology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 116–137.Google Scholar

  • Estlund, D. (2008). Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar

  • Feldman, F. (2012). ‘True and Useful: On the Structure of a Two Level Normative Theory’, Utilitas 24 (2): 151–171.Google Scholar

  • Finnis, J. (1989). ‘Law as Co-Ordination’, Ratio Juris 2 (1): 97–104.Google Scholar

  • Green, L. (2007). ‘The Duty to Govern’, Legal Theory 13 (3–4): 165–185.Google Scholar

  • Griffin, C. (2003). ‘Democracy as a Non-Instrumentally Just Procedure’, Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (1): 111–121.Google Scholar

  • Hare, R.M. (1981). Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar

  • Hart, H.L.A. (1961). The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar

  • Horton, J. (2012). ‘Political Legitimacy, Justice and Consent’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15 (2): 129–148.Google Scholar

  • Krasnoff, L. (1998). ‘Consensus, Stability, and Normativity in Rawls's Political Liberalism’, Journal of Philosophy 95 (6): 269–292.Google Scholar

  • Lang, G. (2004). ‘A Dilemma for Objective Act-Utilitarianism’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics 3 (2): 221–239.Google Scholar

  • Larmore, C. (2013). ‘What Is Political Philosophy?’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (3): 276–306.Google Scholar

  • Lewis, D. (2002). Convention: A Philosophical Study (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar

  • Miller, D. (2003). Political Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar

  • Morris, C. (1998). An Essay on the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar

  • Ord, T. (2009). Beyond Action. D.Phil. thesis, University of Oxford, http://www.amirrorclear.net/academic/papers/beyond-action.pdf (accessed on 16th July 2018).

  • Otsuka, M. (2011). ‘Are Deontological Constraints Irrational?’, in R. Bader and J. Meadowcroft (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Nozick's Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 38–58.Google Scholar

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar

  • Pettit, P. and Brennan, G. (1986). ‘Restrictive Consequentialism’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (4): 438–455.Google Scholar

  • Quong, J. (2011). Liberalism without Perfection (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar

  • Quong, J. (2014). ‘What Is the Point of Public Reason?’, Philosophical Studies 170 (3): 545–553.Google Scholar

  • Railton, P. (1984). ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2): 134–171.Google Scholar

  • Rawls, J. (1955). ‘Two Concepts of Rules’, Philosophical Review 64 (1): 3–32.Google Scholar

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press).Google Scholar

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press).Google Scholar

  • Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar

  • Sandel, M. (1998). Liberalism and the Limits of Justice: Second Edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar

  • Scanlon, T. (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press).Google Scholar

  • Simmons, J. (1999). ‘Justification and Legitimacy’, Ethics 109 (4): 739–771.Google Scholar

  • Stocker, M. (1976). ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’, Journal of Philosophy 73 (14): 453–466.Google Scholar

  • Valentini, L. (2012a). ‘Assessing the Global Order: Justice, Legitimacy, or Political Justice?’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15 (5): 593–612.Google Scholar

  • Valentini, L. (2012b). ‘Justice, Disagreement and Democracy’, British Journal of Political Science 43 (1): 1–23.Google Scholar

  • Varden, H. (2009). ‘Nozick's Reply to the Anarchist’, Law and Philosophy 28 (6): 585–616.Google Scholar

  • Waldron, J. (1996). ‘Kant's Legal Positivism’, Harvard Law Review 109 (7): 1535–1566.Google Scholar

  • Waldron, J. (1999). Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar

  • Wall, S. (2006). ‘Democracy, Authority and Publicity’, Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (1): 85–100.Google Scholar

  • Wall, S. (2007). ‘Democracy and Restraint’, Law and Philosophy 26 (3): 307–342.Google Scholar

  • Walzer, M. (1980). ‘The Moral Standing of States: A Response to Four Critics’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 9 (3): 209–229.Google Scholar

  • Wiland, E. (2007). ‘How Indirect Can Indirect Utilitarianism Be?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2): 275–301.Google Scholar

  • Williams, B. (1973). ‘A Critique of Utilitarianism’, in J.J.C. Smart and B. Williams (eds.). Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 77–150.Google Scholar

  • Williams, B. (2005). ‘Realism and Moralism in Political Theory’, in G. Hawthorn (ed.), In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument (Princeton: Princeton University Press), pp. 1–17.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2018-10-27


Citation Information: Moral Philosophy and Politics, ISSN (Online) 2194-5624, ISSN (Print) 2194-5616, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/mopp-2018-0024.

Export Citation

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in