Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Metaphysica

International Journal for Ontology and Metaphysics

Ed. by Hüntelmann, Rafael / Meixner, Uwe / Tegtmeier, Erwin

Together with Cumpa, Javier

Editorial Board Member: Addis, Laird / Davies, Brian / Hochberg, Herbert / Johansson, Ingvar / Kanzian, Christian / Klima, Gyula / Koons, Robert C / Künne, Wolfgang / Löffler, Winfried / Mulligan, Kevin / Nef, Frederic / Oaklander, Nathan / Oderberg, David / Orilia, Francesco / Plantinga, Alvin / Potrc, Matjaz / Rapp, Christof / Reicher-Marek, Maria Elisabeth / Schantz, Richard / Scholz, Oliver / Seibt, Johanna / Simons, Peter / Smith, Barry / Stoecker, Ralf / Strobach, Niko / Trettin, Käthe / Wachter, Daniel

2 Issues per year


CiteScore 2016: 0.12

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2016: 0.111
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2016: 0.530

Online
ISSN
1874-6373
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Structure and Significance in Metaphysics

Andrew J. Graham
Published Online: 2014-03-13 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/mp-2014-0002

Abstract

This paper discusses recent attempts to defend metaphysics as a worthwhile form of inquiry. According to such views, metaphysics concerns the world’s fundamental structure. I question whether this view can establish that metaphysical disputes are relevant to the rest of our theoretical activities. I take this relevance to be a criterion for whether disputes are worthwhile (or, as I call them, “significant”). I argue that the structure approach is unsatisfactory because appropriately structural disputes need not be worthwhile disputes, and vice versa. So, the structure approach threatens to render metaphysics irrelevant to our broader theorizing, undermining many of its legitimate successes, like the role theorizing about metaphysical modality played in the development of modal logic. Thus these structure-based views provide a poor defense of metaphysics. I then offer an alternative conception of metaphysics as an attempt to understand our most ubiquitous theoretical notions.

Keywords: metaontology; metametaphysics; structure; fundamentality; modality

References

  • Boolos, G. 1993. The Logic of Provability. New York: Cambridge University Press..Google Scholar

  • Carnap, R. 1956. “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology,” reprinted as supplement to Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press..Google Scholar

  • Fine, K. 2009. “The Question of Ontology.” In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, edited by D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman, 157–177. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Johnston, M. 1992. “Reasons and Reductionism.” The Philosophical Review 101(3):589–618.Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Lewis, D. 1968. “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic.” Journal of Philosophy 65:113–26.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Lewis, D. 1983. “New Work for a Theory of Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61:343–77.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • Lewis, D. 1999. “Putnam’s Paradox.” In Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, 56–77. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Quine, W. V. O. 1976. “Three Grades of Modal Involvement.” In The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, 158–176. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Schaffer, J. 2009. “On What Grounds What.” In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, edited by D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman, 347–383. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sider, T. 2001. Four-Dimensionalism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sider, T. 2009. “Ontological Realism.” In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, edited by D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman, 384–423. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Sider, T. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2014-03-13

Published in Print: 2014-04-01


Two views in the vicinity of Sider’s are those defended by Kit Fine (2009) and Jonathan Schaffer (2009). Their views differ from Sider’s in various respects, so it will be simpler to focus on Sider’s view alone, although I think similar criticisms can be extended to their positions as well.

The theory of natural properties that Lewis and Sider accept has broad motivations and wide-ranging applications, as is clear from the discussion in Lewis (1983). I am focusing on its uses in their theories of intentionality, but that shouldn’t be thought of as the whole story. Similarly, the idea of structure needn’t be assimilated to the natural property model, though it does provide a convenient framework for making sense of the idea.

It’s possible to have a similar view where naturalness does not come in degrees. On that view, something is either natural or not. This more absolute conception of naturalness may be more amenable to Sider’s views, since it better captures the idea of the world’s fundamental structure. It’s also hard to make sense of degrees of naturalness when extending the notion of naturalness to cover logical vocabulary, as below.

Compare Sider (2011, sec. 11.3).

There may be another natural interpretation of what it is for a dispute to be structural: it is for a dispute to be about structure or to concern what is structural. That is not what I have in mind in what follows.

Throughout this paper, I am using “significant” and “insignificant” as technical terms, signifying the properties of disputes that make them worthwhile and not worthwhile respectively (which are, in my view, the property of being connected to the rest of our inquiry in the right way and the property of being insular). “Significant” can also carry connotations of being meaningful or genuine, but that is not my intention; the intended reading is that significant disputes matter.

For instance, in computer science, modal logics have been used to help understand distributed systems (a simple model might treat each computer as a possible world and relations of accessibility as network connections between them, allowing theorists to model how information is shared in the system), alongside other, more general applications in modeling computer operations, the evolution of databases over time, error-handling, and so on. In mathematics more generally, modal logic has been useful in clarifying the concept of provability (as in George Boolos (1993)).

Sider also discusses these examples (2011, 73). See also Mark Johnston (1992), where Johnston argues that even if personal identity cannot be reduced to, and doesn’t supervene on, the fundamental physical properties and relations of the sort Derek Parfit (1984) takes to be the only plausible candidates, it doesn’t follow that we shouldn’t care about personal identity or that it isn’t the relation that really matters to us.

I do not mean to suggest that the mere fact that some dispute targets a conceptually deep notion is enough to guarantee its significance (see Sections “Sufficiency” and “An alternative picture” for why I think it is not enough). Some disputes about necessity, for instance, might well be insignificant. In the cases I’ve been discussing, however, we have good reason to think that the disputes do have important connections.

It can be difficult to make sense of this suggestion, but we could imagine that there is some primitive fact about what the correct selection of connectives is, or we might tell a story which privileges one group over the other (perhaps in creating reality, God created conjunction and negation, leaving disjunction to emerge from those as an after-thought).

Of course it’s not inconceivable that how many things there are might matter for some question in mathematics, say, or physics or metaphysics, but on the face of it, without filling in the story, it’s hard to see what that question would be. Nonetheless, some philosophers have held that it does matter, especially finitists in the philosophy of mathematics (of which F. P. Ramsey and the later Wittgenstein may have been examples). The important point for me is that, as I will argue in a moment, the mere fact that how many things there are can be stated in structural terms isn’t enough to show that anything hangs on the issue.


Citation Information: Metaphysica, ISSN (Online) 1874-6373, ISSN (Print) 1437-2053, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/mp-2014-0002.

Export Citation

©2014 by Walter de Gruyter Berlin / Boston. Copyright Clearance Center

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in