Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Open Philosophy

Editor-in-Chief: Harman, Graham


Covered by:
DOAJ - Directory of Open Access Journals
ERIH PLUS

Open Access
Online
ISSN
2543-8875
See all formats and pricing
More options …

Perceptual Spaces Are Sense-Modality- Neutral

Ingvar Johansson
Published Online: 2018-03-24 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0003

Abstract

The paper presents and discusses phenomenological facts about perceptual spaces and percepts, but ends with a few thoughts about possible causal explanations of such spaces. The overarching double-sided hypothesis claims that - from a phenomenological point of view - each individual animal has at each consciously perceived moment of time a sense-modality-neutral perceptual space, and that these perceptual spaces are so-called container spaces. This means, to be concrete, that blind persons, deaf persons, and all perceptually non-handicapped persons have the same kind of phenomenological perceptual space, a sense-modality-neutral container space. The causal reflections bring in James J. Gibson’s work on such matters.

Keywords: Perception; Sense-modalities; Space; Phenomenological facts; Percepts and qualia

References

  • Barwich, Ann-Sophie. Making Sense of Smell: Classifications and Model Thinking in Olfaction Theory. PhD thesis at the University of Exeter, 2013.Google Scholar

  • Barwich, Ann-Sophie. “Measuring the World: Towards a process model of perception.” In Everything Flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology, edited by D. Nicholson and J. Dupré, ch. 17. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018.Google Scholar

  • Berkeley, George. An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision. 1709. Available http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/author/1497.Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Broad, C.D. Kant. An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978.Google Scholar

  • Burge, Tyler. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.Google Scholar

  • Casati, Roberto and Dokic, Jerome. “Sounds.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2010. Available http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sounds/#AspThe. Accessed 23 February 2018. Google Scholar

  • Chastrette, Maurice. “Classification of Odors and Structure-Odor Relationships.” In Olfaction, Taste, and Cognition, edited by C. Rouby et al., 100-16. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.Google Scholar

  • Check, Erika. “People track scents in same way as dogs.” Nature December 17, 2006.Google Scholar

  • Chirimuuta, Mazviita. Outside Color. Perceptual Science and the Puzzle of Color in Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • Clark, Austen. A Theory of Sentience. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.Google Scholar

  • Classen, Constance, Howes, David and Synnott, Anthony. Aroma: The Cultural History of Smell. London: Routledge, 2002.Google Scholar

  • Colyvan, Mark. “Can the Eleatic Principle be Justified?”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28. 1998. 313-36.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Costall, Alan. “1966 and All That: James Gibson and Bottom-Down Theory.” Ecological Psychology 29. 2017, 221-30.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Costall, Alan and Morris, Paul. “The ‘Textbook Gibson’: The Assimilation of Dissidence.” History of Psychology 18. 2015. 1-14.Google Scholar

  • Crombie, A.C. Augustine to Galileo 2. Harmondsworth: Peregrine Books, 1969.Google Scholar

  • Dainton, Barry. Stream of Consciousness. Oxon: Routledge, 2000.Google Scholar

  • Dainton, Barry. Time and Space. Chesham: Acumen, 2001.Google Scholar

  • Dainton, Barry. The Phenomenal Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.Google Scholar

  • de Vignemont, Frederique and Massin, Olivier. “Touch.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, edited by M. Matthen, 294-309. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • Edwards, Michael. Fragrances of the World: The Fragrance Wheel (2018). http://www.fragrancesoftheworld.com/FragranceWheel. Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Egidi, Rosaria. “Marty’s Theory of Space.” In Mind, Meaning and Metaphysics. The Philosophy and Theory of Language of Anton Marty, edited by K. Mulligan, 171-80. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990.Google Scholar

  • Euler, Leonhard. “Reflections on Space and Time.” 1748. Available http://eulerarchive.maa.org/docs/translations/E149tr.Google Scholar

  • pdf; translation of “Réflexions sur l’espace et le temps”, Histoire de l’Academie Royale des sciences et belles lettres 4: 324-33. Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Gibson, James J. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1966.Google Scholar

  • Gibson, James J. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. NewYork: Psychology Press, 2015 [1979].Google Scholar

  • Hardin, C. L. Color for Philosophers. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1988.Google Scholar

  • Henning, Hans. Der Geruch. Leipzig: J.A. Barth, 1916.Google Scholar

  • Husserl, Edmund. “Notizen zur Raumkonstitution.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research I. 1940. 21-37, 217-26.Google Scholar

  • Husserl, Edmund. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1982 [1913].Google Scholar

  • Husserl, Edmund. Thing and Space: Lectures of 1907. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997 [1973].Google Scholar

  • Johansson, Ingvar. “Marty on Grounded Relations.” In Mind, Meaning and Metaphysics. The Philosophy and Theory of Language of Anton Marty, edited by K. Mulligan, 151-6. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990.Google Scholar

  • Johansson, Ingvar. Ontological Investigations (second enl. ed.). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. 2004 [1989].Google Scholar

  • Johansson, Ingvar. “John Searle on Perception-Review.” Metaphysica 18. 2017. 259-75.Google Scholar

  • Johansson, Ingvar. “A Presentation and Defense of Anton Marty’s Conception of Space.” In Anton Marty and Contemporary Philosophy, edited by G. Bacigalupo and H. Leblanc. London: Palgrave Macmillan, forthcoming.Google Scholar

  • Kant, Immanuel. “On the First Ground of the Distinction of Regions of Space” [1768]. In The Philosophy of Right and Left, edited by James Van~Cleve and Robert E. Frederick, 27-33. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991.Google Scholar

  • Kant, Immanuel. Kant’s Inaugural Dissertation of 1770. New York: Columbia College, 1991. Available https://archive.org/details/kantsinauguraldi00kant. Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Katz, David. The World of Colour. London: Kegan Paul, 1935 [1911].Google Scholar

  • Katz, David. The World of Touch. Hilsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1989 [1925].Google Scholar

  • Mac Cumhaill, Clare. Seeing Through. PhD thesis at the University of Edinburgh, 2011.Google Scholar

  • Mac Cumhaill, Clare, “Perceiving Immaterial Paths.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XC. 2015. 687-715.Google Scholar

  • Marty, Anton. Raum und Zeit. Halle: Niemeyer, 1916.Google Scholar

  • Massin, Olivier. L’objectivité du toucher. Métaphysique et Perception. PhD thesis at the University of Provence, 2010.Google Scholar

  • Massin, Olivier and Hämmerli, Marion. “Is Purple a Red and Blue Chessboard? Brentano on Color Mixtures.” The Monist 100. 2017. 37-63.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Matthen, Mohan. “Introduction.”. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, edited by M. Matthen, 1-26. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962 [1945].Google Scholar

  • Michotte, Albert, Thinès, Georges and Crabbe, G. “Amodal Completion of Perceptual Structures.” In Michotte’s Experimental Phenomenology of Perception, edited by G. Thinès, A. Costall and G. Butterworth, 140-67. London: Routledge, 2014 [1991].Google Scholar

  • Mizrahi, Vivian. “Sniff, smell, and stuff.” Philosophical Studies 171. 2014. 233-50.Google Scholar

  • Moore, George Edward. Philosophical Papers. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1959.Google Scholar

  • Moran, Dermot and Cohen, Joseph.) The Husserl Dictionary. London: Continuum IPG, 2012.Google Scholar

  • Mulligan, Kevin. “Perception.” In The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, edited by Smith and Smith, 168-238. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.Google Scholar

  • Nerlich, Graham. The Shape of Space (second rev. ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994 [1976].Google Scholar

  • Nerlich, Graham. “Incongruent Counterparts and the Reality of Space.” Philosophy Compass 4. 2009. 598-613.Google Scholar

  • Nudds, Matthew. “Audition.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, edited by M. Matthen, 275-92. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • O’Callaghan, Casey. “Auditory Perception.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2014. Available http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-auditory/#Spatial. Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Poincaré, Henri. Science and Method. London: Thomas Nelson, 1914 [1908].Google Scholar

  • Roberts, Tom. “A Breath of Fresh Air: Absence and the Structure of Olfactory Perception.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97. 2016, 400-20.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Searle, John. Intentionality. An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.Google Scholar

  • Searle, John. Seeing Things as They Are: A Theory of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • Simons, Peter. “Marty on Time.” In Mind, Meaning and Metaphysics. The Philosophy and Theory of Language of Anton Marty, edited by K. Mulligan, 157-70. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990.Google Scholar

  • Smith, Barry. “Brentano and Marty: An Inquiry into Being and Truth.” In Mind, Meaning and Metaphysics. The Philosophy and Theory of Language of Anton Marty, edited by K. Mulligan, 111-49. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990.Google Scholar

  • Sorensen, Roy. “Perceiving Nothings.” In In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, edited by M. Matthen, 542-63. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.Google Scholar

  • Strawson, Peter. Individuals. London: Methuen, 1964 [1959].Google Scholar

  • Stumpf, Carl. Psychologie und Erkenntnistheorie. 1891. Available https://archive.org/details/PsychologieUndErkenntnistheorie Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Sundström, Pär. “Are Colors Visually Complex?.” In Johanssonian Investigations, edited by C. Svennerlind, J. Almäng, and R. Inghtorsson, 627-39. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, 2013.Google Scholar

  • Tye, Michael. “Qualia.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2015. Available https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/. Accessed 23 February 2018.Google Scholar

  • Wagner, Armin. “Pre-Gibsonian Observations on Active Touch.” History of Psychology 19. 2016. 93-104.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Young, Nick. “Hearing Spaces.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95. 2017. 242-55.Google Scholar

About the article

Received: 2017-09-25

Accepted: 2018-03-01

Published Online: 2018-03-24


Citation Information: Open Philosophy, Volume 1, Issue 1, Pages 14–39, ISSN (Online) 2543-8875, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0003.

Export Citation

© 2018, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. BY-NC-ND 4.0

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in