Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Open Philosophy

Editor-in-Chief: Harman, Graham


Covered by:
DOAJ - Directory of Open Access Journals
ERIH PLUS

Open Access
Online
ISSN
2543-8875
See all formats and pricing
More options …

A Computationally Assisted Reconstruction of an Ontological Argument in Spinoza’s The Ethics

Jack K. Horner
Published Online: 2019-08-21 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2019-0012

Abstract

The comments accompanying Proposition (Prop.) 11 (“God ... necessarily exists”) in Part I of Spinoza’s The Ethics contain sketches of what appear to be at least three more or less distinct ontological arguments. The first of these is problematic even on its own terms. More is true: even the proposition “God exists” (GE), a consequence of Prop. 11, cannot be derived from the definitions and axioms of Part I (the “DAPI”) of The Ethics; thus, Prop. 11 cannot be derived from the DAPI, either. To prove these claims, I use an automated deduction system (ADS) to show that Prop. 11 is independent of the DAPI. I then augment the DAPI with some auxiliary assumptions I believe Spinoza would accept and that sustain an automated derivation of (GE). The results illustrate how an ADS can facilitate the analysis of arguments and yield an apparently novel argument cast in the style of Spinoza.

This article offers supplementary material which is provided at the end of the article.

Keywords: automated deduction; Spinoza; ontological argument

References

  • Anselm. Prosologium. Trans. by S. N. Deane. In St. Anselm: Basic Writings. Second Edition. Chicago: Open Court, 1962.Google Scholar

  • Aquinas. On Being and Essence. Trans. by Armand Maurer, Second Revised Edition. Toronto : The Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1968.Google Scholar

  • Aristotle. Prior Analytics. Trans. by A. J. Jenkinson. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed. by Richard McKeon. New York : Random House, 1941.Google Scholar

  • Aristotle. Metaphysics. Trans. by W. D. Ross. In Richard McKeon, ed. The Basic Works of Aristotle. New York : Random House, 1941.Google Scholar

  • Benzmüller, Cristoph, and Paleo, Bruno W. “Automating Gödel’s ontological proof of God’s existence with higher-order automated theorem provers.” Proceedings of the 2014 European Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 93-98. IOS Press, 2014.Google Scholar

  • Chang, Chen C, and Keisler, H. Jerome. Model Theory. Third Edition. New York : Dover Publications, 2012.Google Scholar

  • Church, Alonzo. Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Part I. Princeton : Princeton University Press, 1956.Google Scholar

  • Cocchiarella, Nino B., and Freund, Max A. Modal Logic: An Introduction to its Syntax and Semantics. Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2008.Google Scholar

  • Descartes. Meditations on First Philosophy. Trans. by L. J. Lafleur. Indianapolis : Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1960.Google Scholar

  • Drews, Samuel, and Albarghouthi, Aws. “Effectively Propositional Interpolants.” In Chaudhuri S., and Farzan A. (eds.). Computer Aided Verification (CAV 2016). Published in Lecture Notes on Computer Science, Vol. 9780. Switzerland: Springer, Cham, 2016, 210-229.Google Scholar

  • Gödel, Kurt. (1970). “Ontological proof”. Reprinted in Solomon Feferman, John W. Dawson, Jr., Warren Goldfarb, Charles Parsons, and Robert N. Solovay (eds.) Kurt Gödel: Collected Works. Volume III. Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1995.Google Scholar

  • Journal of Automated Reasoning. New York: Springer.Google Scholar

  • Kalman, John A. Automated Reasoning with Otter. Princeton : Rinton Press, 2001.Google Scholar

  • Kant. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. by Norman Kemp Smith. New York : St. Martin’s Press LLC, 2007.Google Scholar

  • Leitsch, Alexander. The Resolution Calculus. New York : Springer, 1997.Google Scholar

  • Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. by R. Woodhouse. London : Palgrave, 2004.Google Scholar

  • McCune, William W. prover9 and mace4. http://www.cs.unm.edu/~mccune/prover9/. 2009. Accessed 30 December 2018.

  • Nadler, Stephen. Spinoza’s Ethics: An Introduction. Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2006.Google Scholar

  • Oppenheimer, Paul, and Zalta, Edward. “A computationally-discovered simplification of the ontological argument.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89/2 (2011), 333-349.Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • Oppy, Graham. Ontological Arguments and Belief in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.Google Scholar

  • Oppy, Graham. “Ontological Arguments.” In Edward Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ontological-arguments/. 2011. Accessed 30 December 2018.

  • Quaife, Art. Automated Development of Fundamental Mathematical Theories. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992.Google Scholar

  • Scott, Dana. “Notes in Dana Scott’s Hand.” In Sobel, Jordan H. Logic and Theism: Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God. Cambridge : Cambridge University Press, 2004. Appendix B, 145-146.Google Scholar

  • Spinoza. The Ethics. In Benedict de Spinoza. On the Improvement of the Understanding, The Ethics, Correspondence. Unabridged trans. by R. H. M. Elwes (1883). New York : Dover Publications reprint, 1955.Google Scholar

  • Symons, John F., and Horner, Jack K. “Software error as a limit to inquiry for finite agents: Challenges for the post-human scientist.” In Powers, Tom (ed.) Philosophy and Computing: Essays in Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind, Logic, and Ethics. New York : Springer, 2017.Google Scholar

About the article

Received: 2019-01-08

Accepted: 2019-06-12

Published Online: 2019-08-21

Published in Print: 2019-01-01


Citation Information: Open Philosophy, Volume 2, Issue 1, Pages 211–229, ISSN (Online) 2543-8875, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2019-0012.

Export Citation

© 2019 Jack K. Horner, published by De Gruyter Open. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Public License. BY 4.0

Supplementary Article Materials

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in