Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Open Physics

formerly Central European Journal of Physics

Editor-in-Chief: Seidel, Sally

Managing Editor: Lesna-Szreter, Paulina


IMPACT FACTOR 2018: 1.005

CiteScore 2018: 1.01

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2018: 0.237
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2018: 0.541

ICV 2017: 162.45

Online
ISSN
2391-5471
See all formats and pricing

Access brought to you by:

provisional account

Open Access
More options …
Volume 15, Issue 1

Issues

Volume 13 (2015)

Relativity, anomalies and objectivity loophole in recent tests of local realism

Adam Bednorz
Published Online: 2017-11-10 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/phys-2017-0081

Abstract

Local realism is in conflict with special quantum Bell-type models. Recently, several experiments have demonstrated violation of local realism if we trust their setup assuming special relativity valid. In this paper we question the assumption of relativity, point out not commented anomalies and show that the experiments have not closed objectivity loophole because clonability of the result has not been demonstrated. We propose several improvements in further experimental tests of local realism make the violation more convincing.

Keywords: local realism; Bell theorem

PACS: 03.65.Ta; 03.65.Ud

1 Introduction

In contract to classical physics, quantum mechanics does not provide a direct realistic interpretation. In realism, there exists a joint probability for all possible measurements, even if not simultaneously feasible. The measurements can be choice-dependent. If the choice is located at some spacetime point then local realism means that the probability cannot depend on remote choices – no signaling. If we stick to relativity, remote means spacelike, i.e. beyond the reach of light. Otherwise, remote means simply lack of possible communication (due to either sufficiently short time, large enough distance or lack of known physical communication channel).

Local realism has been questioned by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR) [1], later put by Bell [2] in the form of special inequality, involving at least two observers each choosing between two measurements [3]. Local realism defined by Bell requires existence of a the joint probability distribution for all choice-dependent outcomes. Nowadays, there are many other Bell-type tests [2, 4]. Bell inequality is violated in a simple quantum model. However, it is not so simple to implement the model experimentally. One has to face a lot of problems, such as low detection efficiency, decoherence and fast choice and readouts. Only recently, the experiments started to overcome these problems [5, 6, 7, 8]. Nevertheless, the raw data from these experiments shed light on further possible problems, questioning both the interpretation of the results and completeness of the underlying theory [9, 10].

In this paper we summarize these experiments and the current status of local realism and relativity. We will explain how to improve next experiments to check violation of no-signaling and relativity. In addition we will show the so-called objectivity loophole. Objectivity means that the result of the experiment must get ensured to be objective – clonable arbitrary number of times [11]. Otherwise, one imagine that Eve, a hacker or some uncontrolled physical process alters insecure data to violate a Bell-type inequality. In this case the time tag of the readout should be shifted to the end of the supposed hack which may be enough late to get informed about other party’s choice within lightcone. Such hacking is less likely when several copies exist. Recent experiments have not attempted even making two copies of the results. This is complementary to the freedom of choice loophole. The latter occurs at the start of the experiment and we can only narrow it by complicated random number generations but never close absolutely due to conspiracy in the past. The objectivity loophole occurs at the end of experiment and can be only narrowed by sufficiently large number of independent, secure copies, but never closed completely for an extraordinarily skilled hacker. In fact the loophole is relevant not only for EPR or Bell experiments but also all other experiments, where we want to prove that the readout has been fixed at certain time.

The paper is organized as follows. We start from recalling Bell-type tests used in recent experiments and their assumptions. Then we discuss no-signaling principle in context of relativity and the experimental data. Next we explain insufficient modeling of the recent tests and possible technical issues. Finally, we describe the objectivity loophole and suggestions how to close or narrow it.

2 Bell-type tests

The most known Bell test is due to Clauser, Horne, Shimony, Holt (CHSH) [3], for two observers A and B. Each of them can choose the measurement between 1 and 2 (A) or 3 and 4 (B) the choice-dependent outcome Ai and Bj has values ± 1. Locality means that outcomes depend only on local choice, i.e. A13 = A14 = A1, etc. This assumption is critical because sufficiently slow choice or readout makes it invalid – the observers can ultimately get informed about the other party’s choice. One usually refers here to relativistic bound of speed of light, see Fig. 1 but the examples below do not at all rely on relativity. They are just simple quantum models with assumed states and their evolution.

Spacetime picture of a simple Bell-type test of local realism. Free choices, denoted by small letters generate spatio-temporal lightcones, bounded by speed of light. The measurements, denoted by capital letters must be completed outside of the other party’s choice (A and B) or both (C).
Figure 1

Spacetime picture of a simple Bell-type test of local realism. Free choices, denoted by small letters generate spatio-temporal lightcones, bounded by speed of light. The measurements, denoted by capital letters must be completed outside of the other party’s choice (A and B) or both (C).

Then realism requires existence of the joint positive probability p(A1,A2,B3,B4), yielding the inequality 2A1B3+A1B4+A2B3A2B42(1)

It follows from the fact that A1(B3+B4)+A2(B3B4) is always ± 2. Quantum rule, ABZ=TrA^B^Z^ρ^ for the simultaneously measurable observables (Hermitian) A^,B^ etc., and the (positive, Hermitian, and normalized) state matrix ρ^, allows to predict all here relevant correlations. Taking ρ^ = |ψ〉〈ψ| with Bell states 2|ψ〉 = |+−〉−|−+〉 in the basis |±AB〉 and the observables X^i=eiϕi|+|+eiϕi|+| (in the respective X = A,B subspace) we get Xi = ± 1 and 〈 AiBj〉 = −cos(ϕiϕj). For ϕ1,2,3,4 = (0,π/2,5π/4,3π/4), the inequality (1) is violated as the middle correlator reads 22⋍ 2.84 > 2. Unfortunately, experimental implementation of this model is quite hard. Either the actual outcome has the third value 0 (usually meaning lost particle) or the state decoheres too quickly. In both cases the original inequality is in practice no longer violated. There are at least two counteractions. One is to condition the state by entanglement swapping [13]. The distinguish between main Bell (localized) uppercase states |±A,B〉 and auxiliary communication (traveling) lowercase states |±a,b〉 If observers first generate their local Bell states 2|ψX〉 = |+X,−x〉−|−X,+x〉 for X = A,B, x = a,b (matching upper and lower case letter) and send the lower case a,b states to the observable C^ = |ϕ〉〈ϕ| with 2|ϕ〉 = |+a,–b〉−|−a,+b〉 then the outcome C = 1 heralds the Bell state between A and B. Then even very low efficiency of the heralding does not prevent the Bell test if C is local - independent of all choices, i.e. C = C13 = C14 = C23 = C24. The procedure is preselection and not postselection and so violation of C = 1 conditioned (1) is still correct signature of violation of local realism.

Another solution is to replace CHSH inequality with Eberhard inequality [4] which takes better into account detection efficiency (0 outcomes). The setup is similar to the previous one only Xi = 0, 1 (the case −1 is reassigned also to 0). Positive p yields the inequality p(11,13)p(11,04)p(02,13)p(12,14)0(2)

It follows from the decomposition of probability p(11,13) = p(11,12,13,04)+p(11,02,13)+p(11,12,13,14) while p(11,04)≥ p(11,12,13,04), p(02,13)≥ p(11,02,13) and p(12,14)≥ p(11,12,13,14). Applied to the ideal Bell state with −1 replaced by 0 we get p(1i,1j) = (1 − cos(ϕiϕj))/4 and p(1i,0j) = (1+\cos(ϕiϕj))/4 and the inequality is violated for the same set of angles with the left hand side reading 1/2−1/2⋍ 0.2 > 0.

3 No-signaling and relativity

The local realism assumption of readout independence of remote choice is usually based on relativity. Yet without relativity, there is a universal causality principle that the readout can depend only on earlier choices. Combined now with Lorentz invariance, the dependence is restricted to the light cone, namely r < ct where r/t is the spatial distance/time between the choice and readout, c – speed of light. In relativistic quantum mechanics causality implies compatibility of Heisenberg operators beyond the mutual lightcone (Wightman axiom) [14]. It also leads to no-signaling principle: probability of one observer readout (not correlation with the other one) cannot depend on remote choices. In the Bell case it means p(A14) = p(A13), p(A23) = p(A24), p(B13) = p(B23), p(B14) = p(B24). For entanglement swapping we have additionally p(C13) = p(C14) = p(C23) = p(C24) and even p(A13,C13) = p(A14,C14) etc. No-signaling is directly verifiable in the Bell test and serves as a partial check if locality is indeed true (it cannot rule out hidden signaling affecting only correlations but then anyway the claim of violation of local realism is justified).

In the data of recent tests, two experiments show moderate violation of no signaling [9], noted also by others [10]. In Delft [5] p(Cij) is not equal with 95% confidence level while p(113)≠ p(114) in NIST [6] with similar confidence level. In particular, in Delft N(C14 = 1) = 79 while N(C24 = 1) = 51. Here N(Xij) is the number of actually recorded events, while the prediction is N(Xij) = p(Xij)N for the total number of events N. The difference is even larger when removing the special time window for C = 1 event, then N(C14 = 1) = 218 while N(C24 = 1) = 159. In NIST, N(A13 = 1) = 502339 while N(A23 = 505163) outside the peak region. In Delft violation would be in conflict with relativity while in NIST signaling may be also slower than light although there is no visible borderline. Further experiments and more data are necessary to confirm this finding. It still may be just statistical error.

On the other hand relativity seems to be in conflict with any quantum realism even without Bell example (which – again – does not rely on it). The reason is vanishing of some correlations in vacuum (an invariant state) [15, 16]. For any four-current in spacetime j(x), defining j(p) = d4x eixpj(p) with Minkowski dot product ab = a0b0ab (fourvectors a = (aμ) = (a0,a) with spatial vector a) invariance implies jμ(p)jν(q)=δ(p+q)Gμν(p)(3)

with Gμν = pμ pνξ+gμνη with ξ and η depending only on pp. If realism (positive probability and correlations) holds – even without quantum mechanics, then 0 > η > −(pp)ξ for pp > 0 (timelike) and η = 0, ξ > 0 for pp < 0 (spacelike). Imposing additionally charge conservation jp = 0 we have then ξ = 0 so (3) vanishes completely in this case. This is a serious problem for relativistic quantum field theory because once this correlation is zero, any higher order correlation, involving this quantity must also vanish which is impossible to achieve in a natural attempt of quantum realism [15, 16]. In addition, quantum field theory is often used in a perturbative way, with small interaction coupling. However, no-signaling principle is non-perturbative [14]. Any correction violating relativity will keep speed of light as a signaling limit perturbatively while broken nonperturbatively [16].

It must be also stressed that the recent experiments have not tested relativity, only assumed it. This is formally a loophole although relativity is indeed a fair assumption. Nevertheless, the setups contain obvious possible communication channels (fiber glass) where the information speed is even slower than light using current description. If relativity is wrong, some kind of hidden (so far) superluminal interaction can use this channel. It would be interesting to close these channels during the experiment (single event) to prevent any, even superluminal, interaction using them. Then realistic explanation would require non-locality in the sense of outer communication channels not dedicated to the particular experimental setup.

4 Anomalies

In experimental efforts to violate local realism we have to remember that the violation is based on specific quantum model which should effectively describe the results. Of course local realism can be violated regardless the model behind (we compare the data with a classical local realistic inequality) but we also want to do it in a controllable way to be useful in future, e.g. in quantum cryptography. It is therefore relevant to check how accurate is the theoretical quantum model describing the setup and the data. More importantly, this accuracy boosts the trust in the last, unverifiable, assumption – freedom of choice. Currently the choice is at least partially made by a quantum random number generator and we have to trust that its choices are not affected by the remote party. One usually models the data by two-dimensional Hilbert space for each of observers giving 4 = 2 × 2 total dimension. Then the detector distinguishes only between two states. The probability of a given output depends only on the local choice. The ratio between probabilities for different choices, p(A1 = 1)/p(A2 = 1) cannot depend on any other parameter, also when binning the time-tags of detection. However, in Vienna [7] clearly the ratio depends on the binning, see Fig. 2 (or [9] for B).The only solution within quantum mechanics is to increase the dimension of the space. It is not particularly unreasonable, e.g. photons can have additional orbital degrees of freedom, apart from two-state polarization, namely their direction of motion. The Pockels cell, normally changing only polarization, may also change the direction and the final photodetector efficiency may depend on this direction. Formally it can be realized by introducing auxiliary states |k〉, k = 0,…n−1 for each observer. then the total space basis is |j,±;k,±〉 (2n × 2n states). Now suppose the initial Bell state reads |+0,−0〉−|−0,+0〉 and choice makes a local unitary rotation U^ in the basis ± but also rotation |j〉〈0|+|0〉 〈 j| for j equal the choice index (alternatively, one of choices can lead to null, identity operation) Then there are two different states reaching the detector A, |+1〉 and |+2〉. Now the outcome probability can additionally depend on the choice. This mechanism can explain difference observed in Vienna. However, it does not say anything about its physical origin (e.g. Pockels cell mechanics). To quantify it one should rerun the experiment, examining the influence of Pockels cell. It will not only help to find a better quantum model for violation of local realism but also ensure that the process is well described within known microscopic theory of optical setups. Otherwise, this analysis will help to identify novel quantum effect which might need explanation beyond current theory.

Scaled number of detection events at A in Vienna depending
on local choice, in 4ns bins
Figure 2

Scaled number of detection events at A in Vienna depending on local choice, in 4ns bins

In Munich [8], the data also show discrepancy with the simplest Bell model. In this case, all Bell correlators should be equal for choice-independent efficiency and visibility while the data show clear inequality (about 4 standard deviations). For instance N(AB23 = +/−) = 251/1012 while N(AB24 = +/−) = 932/242. In this case however, the explanation does not even need larger space. It may be just due to the fact the state in not exactly Bell’s (maximally entangled). In general it can be anything in the |±±〉 basis. Moreover, the angles ϕ may deviate from the expected values. Although this is a reasonable explanation, there is no comment and estimate about the discrepancy in the paper.

5 Objectivity loophole

Recent experiments made considerable progress in violation local realism because they closed simultaneously two important loopholes - detection and communication. Detection loophole was common for photon-based experiments with low detection efficiency. For small rate of detected photons the additional outcome 0 (no-detection or lost photon) makes impossible to violate (1). Violation is then only possible making an addition, unverifiable assumption of fair sampling, namely, that 0 outcome occurs randomly and so it can be removed form analysis. On the other hand communication of locality loophole occurs whenever the distance between A and B is so small that the signal about the choice can reach the other party before completing the readout.

The recent experiments [5, 6, 7, 8] cannot close the freedom of choice loophole, which means that the choice is in fact predetermined or simply determined earlier than claimed. An attempt to close it by cosmic rays [17] opens again detection loophole because of low fraction of detected photons. The loophole occurs also due to assumed readout time, determined experimentally by the time taggers. The loophole is somewhat philosophical because there is no objective criterion for choice and readout times. Even cosmic photons will not be fully convincing, after all one has to trust that the photons are indeed uncorrelated (and that they were not swapped with other, correlated ones). Therefore, it is rather the question of reaching practical thresholds.

However, one should obey the criterion of objective readout, neglected so far experimentally, i.e. the clonability of the outcome. Objective realism means that we can copy the result of the measurements an arbitrary number of times (broadcasting) [11]. Operationally, it means that the positive operator-valued measure (POVM) [12] describing the measurement by creating a new outcome-dependent state ρ^K^ρ^K^ (Kraus operators K^ [18]), is not just a set of projections, K^=P^x=|xx|withxP^x=I^ (identity) in some basis x. Broadcasting or cloning essentially demands a large set of copies |x1,x2,…,xm〉 with the number of copies m → ∞ and K^x=|x1=x,x2=x,m=xx|.(4)

Without demonstrating clonability, an experiment has the objectivity loophole left open. This means that a hacker, or simply some unspecified subluminal interaction can change the registered value after the readout time tag using the information about the other party’s choice. Then the inequality (1) or (2) is violated but the communication has lasted longer and the final (hacker’s) time tag is already within lightcone. Violation of Bell-type inequalities in this case does not refute local realism. Of course in experimental practice we can achieve only a finite number of copies. A fair approach to objectivity would require making at least two independent copies. It should be relatively simple to implement rerunning recent experiments. Once the readout is complete, it should be copied to an independent storage (computer) with the final time tag after storing both copies, see Fig. 3. In the data analysis one should check if the copies are the same. It will not only help to demonstrate closing the loophole but also prove security of the data. If violation of local realism is useful for quantum cryptography, the whole process must be protected from hacking, e.g. modifying the data after the readout. It may be less likely to hack two independent storages than a single one.

Closing objectivity loophole in practice. Notation as in Fig. 1. Information about both the choice and readout, including timetags, must be stored in several copies, preferably independent computers, indicated by arrows, except arrows indicating influence of the choice on the measurement (not vice versa!). Data processing after finishing the experimental run should include comparison between copies. All events with difference between copies must be excluded from considerations.
Figure 3

Closing objectivity loophole in practice. Notation as in Fig. 1. Information about both the choice and readout, including timetags, must be stored in several copies, preferably independent computers, indicated by arrows, except arrows indicating influence of the choice on the measurement (not vice versa!). Data processing after finishing the experimental run should include comparison between copies. All events with difference between copies must be excluded from considerations.

6 Conclusion

Recent experimental Bell-type test rely on several, hard to verify assumptions, including relativity, freedom of choice, and objectivity, constituting formal loopholes. We suggest to get free from relativity assumption by closing communication channels, and show objectivity by cloning the results immediately after each event. At least the latter should not be technically demanding, requiring simply storing data on several computers. In addition, anomalies in the data need explanation by some diagnostic run, capturing yet unspecified effect of Pockels cells or other devices in the setup.

Acknowledgement

The objectivity loophole has been inspired by discussion with J. Korbicz, P. Mironowicz and R. Horodecki in Sopot, Poland, in May 2017.

References

  • [1]

    Einstein A., Podolsky B., Rosen N., Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?, Phys. Rev., 1937, 47, 777. Google Scholar

  • [2]

    Bell, J.S., On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox, Physics (Long Island City, N.Y.), 1964, 1, 195; Shimony A., Bell’s Theorem plato.stanford.edu/entries/bell-theorem/. Google Scholar

  • [3]

    Clauser J.F., Horne M.A., Shimony A. and Holt R.A., Proposed Experiment to Test Local Hidden-Variable Theories, Phys. Rev. Lett., 1969, 23, 880. CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [4]

    Eberhard P.H., Background level and counter efficiencies required for a loophole-free Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen experiment, Phys. Rev. A, 1993, 47, R747. CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [5]

    Hensen B. et al., Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres. Nature, 2015, 526, 682 CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • [6]

    Shalm L.K. et al., Strong Loophole-Free Test of Local Realism, Phys. Rev. Lett., 2015, 115, 250402 Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [7]

    Giustina M. et al., Significant-Loophole-Free Test of Bell’s Theorem with Entangled Photons, Phys. Rev. Lett., 2015, 115, 250401 CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • [8]

    Rosenfeld W., Event-Ready Bell Test Using Entangled Atoms Simultaneously Closing Detection and Locality Loopholes, Phys. Rev. Lett., 2017, 119, 010402. Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [9]

    Bednorz A., Analysis of assumptions of recent tests of local realism, Phys. Rev. A, 2017, 95, 042118. Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [10]

    Adenier G., Khrennikov A. Yu., Test of the no-signaling principle in the Hensen loophole-free CHSH experiment, arXiv:1606.00784; Graft D.A., Anomalous Postselection in the Hensen et al. Bell Test, arXiv:1608.02404; Larsson J.-A., private communication (2016). Google Scholar

  • [11]

    Korbicz J.K., Horodecki P., Horodecki R., Objectivity in a Noisy Photonic Environment through Quantum State Information Broadcasting, Phys. Rev. Lett., 2014, 112, 120402. Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [12]

    Wiseman H.M., Milburn G.J., Quantum Measurement and Control (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009). Google Scholar

  • [13]

    Żukowski M., Zeilinger A., Horne M. A. & Ekert A. K., ”Event-ready-detectors” Bell experiment via entanglement swapping, Phys. Rev. Lett., 1993, 71, 4287. CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [14]

    R. F. Streater and A. S. Wightman, PCT, spin and statistics, and all that (Benjamin, New York, 1964) Google Scholar

  • [15]

    Bednorz A., Objective Quantum Realism, New J. Phys. 2015, 17, 093006. CrossrefWeb of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • [16]

    Bednorz A., Objective realism and freedom of choice in relativistic quantum field theory, Phys. Rev. D, 2016, 94, 085032 Web of ScienceCrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • [17]

    Handsteiner J. et al., Cosmic Bell Test: Measurement Settings from Milky Way Stars, Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 118, 060401 Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar

  • [18]

    Kraus K., States, Effects and Operations (Springer, Berlin, 1983). Google Scholar

About the article

Received: 2017-09-10

Accepted: 2017-09-28

Published Online: 2017-11-10


Citation Information: Open Physics, Volume 15, Issue 1, Pages 692–696, ISSN (Online) 2391-5471, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/phys-2017-0081.

Export Citation

© 2017 Adam Bednorz. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. BY-NC-ND 4.0

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in