Jump to ContentJump to Main Navigation
Show Summary Details
More options …

Theoretical Linguistics

An Open Peer Review Journal

Editor-in-Chief: Krifka, Manfred

Ed. by Gärtner, Hans-Martin

4 Issues per year


IMPACT FACTOR 2016: 0.864
5-year IMPACT FACTOR: 1.744

CiteScore 2017: 0.70

SCImago Journal Rank (SJR) 2017: 0.457
Source Normalized Impact per Paper (SNIP) 2017: 1.318

Online
ISSN
1613-4060
See all formats and pricing
More options …
Volume 43, Issue 1-2

Issues

Fictional Names in Psychologistic Semantics

Emar Maier
Published Online: 2017-06-08 | DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/tl-2017-0001

Abstract

Fictional names pose a difficult puzzle for semantics. How can we maintain that Frodo is a hobbit, while admitting that Frodo does not exist? To dissolve this paradox, I propose a way to formalize the interpretation of fiction as ‘prescriptions to imagine’ (Walton 1990) within a psychologistic semantic framework in the style of Kamp (1990). In the context of an information exchange, the interpretation of an assertion triggers a dynamic update of a belief component in the interpreter’s mental state, while in the context of a fictional narrative, a statement like Frodo is a hobbit triggers an update of an imagination component. In the computation of these updates, proper names – referential, empty, or fictional – are uniformly analyzed as presupposition triggers. The possibility of different attitude components in a single mental state sharing discourse referents and thereby referentially depending on each other ultimately allows us to account for the central paradox of fictional names and related puzzles.

Keywords: semantics; fiction; imagination; reference; (fictional) proper names; mental states; mental files; (propositional) attitudes; presupposition; Discourse Representation Theory

References

  • Anderson, John & Christian Lebiere. 1998. The atomic components of thought. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar

  • Asher, Nicholas. 1986. Belief in discourse representation theory. Journal of Philosophical Logic 15(2). 127–189. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Bach, Kent. 1987. Thought and reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Bauer, Matthias & Sigrid Beck. 2014. On the meaning of fictional texts. In D. Gutzmann et al. (eds.), Approaches to meaning, 250–275. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar

  • Bonomi, Andrea & Sandro Zucchi. 2003. A pragmatic framework for truth in fiction. Dialectica 57(2). 103–120. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Brasoveanu, Adrian & Jakub Dotlacil. 2015. Incremental and predictive interpretation. Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 25. 57–81. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Cohen, Ariel & Manfred Krifka. 2014. Superlative quantifiers and meta-speech acts. Linguistics and Philosophy 37(1). 41–90. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Currie, Gregory. 1990. The nature of fiction. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar

  • Eckardt, Regine. 2014. The semantics of free indirect speech. How texts allow us to mind-read and eaves-drop. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar

  • Edelberg, Walter. 1992. Intentional identity and the attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy 15(6). 561–596.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Elbourne, Paul. 2010. The existence entailments of definite descriptions. Linguistics and Philosophy 33(1). 1–10. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Farkas, Donka & Kim Bruce. 2009. On reacting to assertions and polar questions. Journal of Semantics 27(1). 81–118. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Fauconnier, Gilles. 1994. Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar

  • van Fraassen, Bas. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon. doi:10.1093/0198244274.001.0001.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Frank, Anette & Hans Kamp. 1997. On context dependence in modal constructions. Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 7. 151–168. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Frege, Gottlob. 1892. Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100(1). 25–50.Google Scholar

  • Friend, Stacie. 2007. Fictional characters. Philosophy Compass 2(2). 141–156. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Friend, Stacie. 2011. The great beetle debate: A study in imagining with names. Philosophical Studies 153(2). 183–211. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Geach, Peter. 1967. Intentional identity. The Journal of Philosophy 64(20). 627–632.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Geurts, Bart. 1997. Good news about the description theory of names. Journal of Semantics 14(4). 319–348. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Geurts, Bart. 1999. Presuppositions and pronouns. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar

  • Groenendijk, Jeroen & Martin Stokhof. 1991. Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy 14(1). 39–100. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Heim, Irene. 1982. On the semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Amherst: University of Massachusetts dissertation. http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/Tk0ZmYyY

  • Heim, Irene. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL) 2. 114–126.Google Scholar

  • Heim, Irene. 1992. Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics 9(3). 183–221. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kamp, Hans. 1990. Prolegomena to a structural account of belief and other attitudes. In A. Anderson & J. Owens (eds.), Propositional attitudes: The role of content in logic, language, and mind, 27–90. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar

  • Kamp, Hans. 2011. Representing De Se thoughts and their reports. http://nasslli2012.com/files/kamp_2011.pdf

  • Kamp, Hans. 2015. Using proper names as intermediaries between labelled entity representations. Erkenntnis 80(2). 263–312. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kamp, Hans, Josef Van Genabith & Uwe Reyle. 2003. Discourse representation theory. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, vol. 10, 125–394. Heidelberg: Springer. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kaplan, David. 1973. Bob and Carol and Ted and Alice. In J. Hintikka et al. (eds.), Approaches to natural language, Dordrecht: Springer. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 481–614. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Karttunen, Lauri. 1973. Presuppositions of compound sentences. Linguistic Inquiry 4(2). 169–193.Google Scholar

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1981. The notional category of modality. In H. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (eds.), Words, worlds, and contexts, 38–74. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar

  • Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Kripke, Saul. 2011. Vacuous names and fictional entities. In S. Kripke (ed.), Philosophical troubles, 52–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Lewis, David. 1978. Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly 15(1). 37–46.Google Scholar

  • Maier, Emar. 2014. Mixed quotation: The grammar of apparently transparent opacity. Semantics and Pragmatics 7(7). 1–67. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Maier, Emar. 2015a. Parasitic attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy 38(3). 205–236. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Maier, Emar. 2015b. Reference, binding, and presupposition: Three perspectives on the semantics of proper names. Erkenntnis 80(2). 313–333. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Maier, Emar. 2016. Referential dependencies between conflicting attitudes. Journal of Philosophical Logic 1–27. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1904. Über Gegenstandstheorie. In A. Meinong (ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie, 1–51. Leipzig: Barth.Google Scholar

  • Ninan, Dilip. 2008. Imagination, content, and the self, MIT dissertation.Google Scholar

  • Ninan, Dilip. 2012. Counterfactual attitudes and multi-centered worlds. Semantics and Pragmatics 5. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Perry, John. 1980. A problem about continued belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61. 317–332.Google Scholar

  • Perry, John. 2001. Reference and reflexivity. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar

  • Quine, Willard V O. 1948. On what there is. Review of Metaphysics 2(1948). 21–38.Google Scholar

  • Radford, Colin. 1975. How can we be moved by the fate of Anna Karenina? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 49. 67–93. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106870.

  • Recanati, François. 2012. Mental files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

  • Roberts, Craige. 1987. Modal subordination, anaphora, and distributivity. Amherst: UMass dissertation. http://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations/AAI8710499/.

  • Roberts, Craige. 1989. Modal subordination and pronominal anaphora in discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy 12(6). 683–721. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Roberts, Craige. 1996. Anaphora in intensional contexts. In S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, 215–246. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar

  • van Rooy, Robert. 2000. Anaphoric relations across attitude contexts. In K. Von Heusinger & U. Egli (eds.), Reference and anaphoric relations, 157–181. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1905. On denoting. Mind 14(56). 479–493. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2248381Crossref

  • Sæbø, Kjell Johan. 2012. Reports of specific indefinites. Journal of Semantics 30(3). 267–314. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Sainsbury, Mark. 2005. Reference without referents. Oxford: OUP. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Sainsbury, Mark. 2011. Fiction and acceptance-relative truth, belief and assertion. In F. Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in fiction, 38–137. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar

  • Salis, Fiora. 2013. Fictional names and the problem of intersubjective identification. Dialectica 67(3). 283–301. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • van der Sandt, Rob. 1992. Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics 9(4). 333–377. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Searle, John. 1975. The logical status of fictional discourse. New Literary History 6(2). 319–332. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Searle, John. 2001. Modals and Illocutionary forces – Reply to Zaefferer. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 55(216). 286–290. https://www.cairn.info/revue-internationale-de-philosophie-2001-2-page-277.htm

  • Shan, Chung-chieh. 2007. Causal reference and inverse scope as mixed quotation. Amsterdam Colloquium 16. 199–204. http://www.illc.uva.nl/AC/AC2007/uploaded_files/proceedings-AC07.pdf

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 1970. Pragmatics. Synthese 22(1–2). 272–289.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 1984. Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar

  • Stone, Matthew. 1997. The anaphoric parallel between modality and tense. http://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/79

  • Thomasson, Amie. 1999. Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar

  • Walton, Kendall. 1990. Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

  • Wechsler, Stephen. 2010. What ‘you’ and ‘I’ mean to each other: Person indexicals, self-ascription, and theory of mind. Language 86(2). 332–365. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

  • Yanovich, Igor. 2011. The problem of counterfactual de re attitudes. Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 21. 56–75. http://elanguage.net/journals/index.php/salt/article/view/21.56

  • Zalta, Edward. 1983. Abstract objects: An introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar

  • Zalta, Edward. 2000. The road between pretense theory and abstract object theory. In T. Hofweber & A. Everett (eds.), Empty names, fiction, and the puzzles of non-existence, 117–147. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar

  • Zeevat, Henk. 1999. Demonstratives in discourse. Journal of Semantics 16(4). 279–313. doi:.CrossrefGoogle Scholar

About the article

Published Online: 2017-06-08

Published in Print: 2017-06-27


Citation Information: Theoretical Linguistics, Volume 43, Issue 1-2, Pages 1–45, ISSN (Online) 1613-4060, ISSN (Print) 0301-4428, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/tl-2017-0001.

Export Citation

© 2017 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston.Get Permission

Comments (0)

Please log in or register to comment.
Log in