1 Introduction
Nonlinear expectations have been a prominent topic in mathematical economics ever since the famous Allais paradox. Typical examples are monetary risk measures introduced in [1, 2], Choquet expectations developed in [3], g-expectations and G-expectations established and studied by [4–10] respectively.
The theory of sublinear expectation, an important and a special nonlinear expectation, is not based on a given (linear) probability space. We all know that, under some mild continuity conditions, each sublinear expectation 𝔼 has a robust representation as the supremum of a subset of probability measures. It thus provides a new way to describe the uncertainties.
In a financial context, when facing risks one often uses the stochastic orders to compare the “good or bad” between the portfolios. In this case, a probability measure is given on the set of scenarios, so we can focus on the resulting payoff or loss distributions. The comparison of financial risks plays an important role for both regulators and agents in financial markets. Under the framework of a classical probability space, based on expected utility theory developed by [11], lots of elegant results about the stochastic orders have been obtained. For example, in the stochastic order theory it has been shown that the monotonic order is equivalent to saying that one risk position is preferred over the other by all decision makers who have increasing real functions for which the expectations exist. For more details and properties of stochastic orders, see [12, 13].
Motivated by the classical stochastic orders, the object of this paper is to explore the uncertainty orders for random vectors in a sublinear expectation space. These uncertainty orders will provide useful criterions for describing the comparisons of the uncertainty degrees between two random vectors on the sublinear expectation space.
We establish the uncertainty orders in the sublinear expectation space from two different viewpoints. One is from the sublinear operator viewpoint. We give some definitions of uncertainty orders such as monotonic orders, convex orders and increasing convex orders. Then we use these uncertainty orders to derive the characterizations for maximal distributions, G-normal distributions and G-distributions, which are the most important random vectors in the theory of sublinear expectation space.
On the other hand, we study the uncertainty orders in the sublinear expectation space by a family of probability measures 𝒫 induced by the sublinear expectation 𝔼. We can define the capacity space from 𝒫, then we get some characterizations with the help of the recent results about capacity orders obtained by [14, 15] in the capacity space. Besides, we also give the characterization of uncertainty orders by distortion functions.
The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we first introduce some preliminaries about the sublinear expectation space. Then we give the definitions of uncertainty orders from the sublinear operator viewpoint, and establish some characterizations for maximal distributions, G-normal distributions and G-distributions. In Section 3, we introduce the other viewpoint of characterizations for uncertainty orders in the sublinear expectation space by using some terminologies of a capacity space. We conclude the paper in Section 4.
2 Characterizations of uncertainty orders from the sublinear operator viewpoint
We first present some preliminaries of sublinear expectation space theory. Then we give the definitions of uncertainty orders in the sublinear expectation space. More details for the first subsection can be found in [6, 8].
2.1 Sublinear expectation spaces
where m depends only on φ.
(see [8]). A sublinear expectation 𝔼 on 𝓗 is a functional 𝔼 : 𝓗 → ℝ satisfying the following properties: for all X, Y ∈ 𝓗, we have
- (i)Monotonicity: 𝔼[X] ≥ 𝔼[Y] if X ≥Y.
- (ii)Constant preserving: 𝔼[c] = c for c ∈ ℝ.
- (iii)Subadditivity: 𝔼[X + Y] ≤ 𝔼[X] + 𝔼[Y].
- (iv)Positive homogeneity: 𝔼[λX] = λ𝔼[X] for λ ≥ 0.
The triple (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼) is called a sublinear expectation space.
The triple (ℝn, Cl.Lip (ℝn), 𝔽X) forms a sublinear expectation space. 𝔽X is called the distribution of X. Let Y be another n-dimensional random vector on (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼), we denote
Let X, X̅ be two n-dimensional random vectors on a sublinear expectation space (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼). X̅ is called an independent copy of X if
where η̅ is an independent copy of η. In particular, for n = 1, we denote
where X̅ is an independent copy of X. In particular, for n = 1, we denote
where (X̅ η̅) is an independent copy of (X η) For n = 1, we denote
2.2 Characterizations from the sublinear operator viewpoint
Throughout the following paper, we interpret the risk positions as loss random vectors. Motivated by the definitions of stochastic orders in a probability space, we give the definitions of uncertainty orders in a sublinear expectation space. We then use these uncertainty orders to derive the characterizations for maximal distributions, G-normal distributions and G-distributions.
Let (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼) be a sublinear expectation space. Let X, Y be two n-dimensional random vectors on (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼).
- (i)X is said to precede Y in the monotonic order sense under 𝔼, denoted by
, if for all increasing functions φ ∈ Cl.Lip (ℝn), we have - (ii)X is said to precede Y in the convex order sense under 𝔼, denoted by
, if (1) holds for all convex functions φ ∈ Cl.Lip (ℝn) - (iii)X is said to precede Y in the increasing convex order sense under 𝔼, denoted by
, if (1) holds for all increasing convex functions φ ∈ Cl.Lip (ℝn).
From the definitions of uncertainty orders as above, we can see that the uncertainty orders only involve the distributions of random vectors X and Y, thus we can also consider the random vectors X and Y from the different sublinear expectation spaces.
Compared with the stochastic orders, here we impose an extra restriction condition - 𝔼[−φ(X)] ≤ 𝔼[−φ(Y)] on the uncertainty orders, which is a redundant condition in the linear probability space.
where Θ is a family of probability measures on (ℝn, 𝓑(ℝn)). In this sense, we say
The internals [μ, μ̅] and [σ2;σ̅2] characterize the mean-uncertainty and the variance-uncertainty of X respectively.
From Definition 2.4 of the uncertainty orders, we easily obtain that for another loss random variable Y in (Ω, 𝓗, 𝔼), with the mean-uncertainty interval [vv̅] and the variance-uncertainty interval [ρ2, ρ̅2],
- –if
or , then μ̅ ≤ v̅ and μ ≤ v̅. - –if
then μ̅ = v̅, μ = v, σ̅2 ≤ ρ̅2 and σ2 ≤ ρ2.
In the following three theorems we show that for some particular distributions the above necessary conditions are also the sufficient conditions. And these distributions are very important in the sublinear expectation space theory.
Let
- (i)
and μ ≤ v. - (ii)
and μ = v, i.e., .
(i) From the definitions of the monotonic order and the increasing convex order,
Thus we have
(ii) It is obvious that
Let
- (i)
and σ ≤ ρ2i.e., . - (ii)
and σ2 ≤ ρ2.
(i)
Similarly we can get
Taking an increasing concave function φ(x) = -x ̅, we can derive σ̅2 ≥ ρ̅2 and σ2 ≥ ρ2 using the arguments as φ(x) = x+.
We conclude from the above that σ̅2 = ρ̅2 and σ2 = ρ2, i.e.,
(ii) Clearly we have
It only needs to show that σ̅2 ≤ ρ̅2 and σ2 ≤ ρ2 ⟹
By combining (6) with (8), we get
Let
- (i)
, if and only ifμ̅ ≤ v̅, μ ≤ v, σ̅2 = ρ̅2andσ2 ≤ ρ2. - (ii)
, if and only ifμ̅ = v̅, μ ≤ v, σ̅2 ≤ ρ̅2andσ2 ≤ ρ2. - (iii)
, if and only ifμ̅ ≤ v̅, μ ≤ v, σ̅2 ≤ ρ̅2andσ2 ≤ ρ2.
The “only if” parts are the combinations of the results of Theorem 2.7 and Theorem 2.8. In fact, for example, if
For the proof of the converse implications, the key ideas are both the applications of the comparison theorem of the viscosity solutions to G-equations. We only show the case (iii). Cases (i) and (ii) are verified by an analogous argument.
where
By combining (12) with (14), we obtain
In the classical linear expectation space, for the stochastic orders’ results to the normal distributions, the reader can refer to [12] and [16]. We list the results as follows. Let
- –
, if and only ifμ ≤ v, σ2 = ρ2, - –
, if and only ifμ = v, σ2 ≤ ρ2, - –
, if and only ifμ ≤ v, σ2 ≤ ρ2,
Hence, our results generalize the classical results.
Theorem 2.9 looks like just combining stochastic orders’ results of two normal distributions
In this subsection, we introduce some uncertainty orders in the sublinear expectation space. Here we only consider some random variables with special distributions. It is not easy to characterize other distributions. For more properties or computations, the readers can refer to [17, 18].
3 Characterizations of uncertainty orders from the probability measures viewpoint
In this section, we first list some properties of a capacity and quantile functions. We then introduce the recent results of uncertainty orders in the capacity space introduced by [14, 15]. We also establish some characterizations by distortion functions. Finally, we derive the characterizations for uncertainty orders by capacity space theory, induced by sublinear expectation space.
3.1 Quantile functions and risk measures
Let (Ω, ℱ) be a measurable space, and for simplicity we only consider the situation bounded random variables. Let L∞ = L∞ (Ω, ℱ) be the space of bounded ℱ-measurable functions, endowed with the supremum norm ∥·∥.
Firstly, we introduce some properties of set functions μ : ℱ →[0, 1] by [3]:
- –Monotonicity: if A, B ∈ ℱ and A ⊆ B, then μ(A) ≤ μ(B);
- –Normalization: if μ (∅) = 0 and μ(Ω) = 1;
- –Continuous from below: if An, A ∈ ℱ, and An ↑ A, then μ(An) ↑ μ(A);
- –Continuous from above: if An, A ∈ ℱ, and An ↓ A, then μ(An) ↓ μ(A).
Now we introduce the definitions of capacity and Choquet integral (see, for instance, [19], [3]).
A set function μ : ℱ → [0, 1] is called a capacity if it is monotonic, normalized and continuous from below and continuous from above.
We call μ(X) the Choquet integral of X with respective to the capacity μ.
We call Gμ, X the decreasing distribution function of X with respective to μ. Taking into account the continuity property from below of the capacity μ, we derive that Gμ, X is right continuous. We introduce the definition of quantile functions of X with respect to μ by [3].
And
Any two quantile functions coincide for all levels λ, except on at most a countable set. We also have the following properties about the quantile functions of X under the capacity μ (see Chapter 1 and Chapter 4 of [3]). Note that (iv) of Lemma 3.5 holds here because the capacity is continuous from below and above, the reader can obtain a similar proof of Lemma A.23 in [12], see also Remark 2.4 in [15].
Let μ be a capacity and X ∈L∞, we have
- (i)Ğμ, X (·) is a decreasing function;
- (ii)If v is an another capacity and Y ∈ L∞, such that Gv, Y ≤ Gμ, X, thenĞv, Y ≤ Ğμ, Xexcept on at most a countable set;
- (iii)
- (iv)If u is an increasing function, then Ğμ, u(X) = u ∘ Ğμ, X except on at most a countable set.
Note that VaR of a financial position X ∈ L∞ under a given probability measure P on (Ω, ℱ) is the quantile function of the distribution of X. We give the following definitions, which generalize the definitions of VaR and AVaR under a priori probability measure. These definitions can also be found in [14, 15], where Grigorova used the different notations but the economic implications are the same.
We list some concepts of uncertainty orders under a capacity introduced by Grigorova. See Definition 2.7 and Definition 3.1 in [15].
Let μ be a capacity. Let X and Y be two losses positions in L∞.
- (i)X is said to precede Y in the increasing convex ordering under μ, denoted by
, if for all increasing and convex function ϕ : ℝ → ℝ - (ii)X is said to precede Y in monotone ordering under μ, denoted by
, if for all increasing function ϕ : ℝ → ℝ
Some characterizations about these uncertainty orders were considered in [14, 15], see Propositions 2.6–2.8 and Proposition 3.1 in [15].
([15]) Let μ be a capacity, X, Y ∈ L∞. The following statements hold.
- (i)
for any b ∈ ℝ. - (ii)
for any λ ∈ (0, 1) - (iii)
In Proposition 3.10, we use our notations. In fact, γX(t), in the Proposition 2.6 of [15], is equal to our Ğμ, –X (1 - t) ∀t ∈ (0, 1), thus (ii) and (iii) of our claims hold by simple transformation.
Here, we give an another characterization of the uncertainty orders
Motivated by [22], we give the characterizations of the uncertainty orders
A distortion function is defined as a non-decreasing function g :[0, 1] → [0, 1] such that g(0) = 0 and g(1) = 1.
Let μ be a capacity. For two losses X, Y ∈ L∞
- (i)
for all distortion functions g. - (i)
for all concave distortion functions g.
(i) The “⟹” implication follows immediately from Gμ, X(x) ≥ Gμ, Y (x) and the non-decreasing property of any distortion function.
Hence, g ∘ μ(X) = VaRμ, λ(X). Then by Proposition 3.10(iii), we have
Then by Proposition 3.10, we have
“⟹” Any concave distortion functions (the concave distortion function may be not continuous at the point 0). Without loss of generality, we only need to show g ∘ μ(X) ≥ g ∘ μ (Y) for all continuous concave distortion functions g.
By Proposition 3.10, we thus obtain g ∘ μ(X) ≥ g ∘ μ(Y) for all continuous concave piecewise linear distortion functions g.
For any continuous concave distortion function g, there exists an increasing sequence of continuous concave piecewise linear distortion functions gn such that limn→∞gn(x) = g(x) for all x ∈ [0, 1]. Since gn ∘ μ(X) ≥ gn ∘ μ(Y) for all n, by monotone convergence theorem, we have g ∘ μ(X) ≥ g ∘ μ(Y). The proof is complete. □
If μ is a sub modular capacity, then for any concave distortion function g, g ∘ μ(−·) is a coherent risk measure on L∞. In particular, for λ ∈ (0, 1], AVaRμ, λ(−·) is a coherent risk measure.
is a sub modular capacity.
Multiplying both sides with (μ(A)− μ(A ∩ B)) derives the result.
Let g be defined by (17), we then find that AVaRμ, λ(·) = g ∘ μ(·) for a continuous concave function. Hence AVaRμ, λ(−·) is a coherent risk measure. The proof is complete. □
3.2 Characterizations from the probability measures viewpoint
is a capacity. Thus (Ω, 𝓑(Ω), μ) become a capacity space.
where VaRQ, λ(X) = inf{x|Q(X > x) ≤ λ} and
hold.
Finally, from the characterizations results of uncertainty orders in Propositions 3.10–3.13, we conclude the following theorems.
Let μ be a capacity induced by a family of probability measures 𝒫, which is determined by the sublunar expectation 𝔼. Let X; Y ∈ 𝓗. The following statements are equivalent.
- (i)μ(𝜙(X)) ≥ μ(𝜙(Y)) for all increasing and convex function 𝜙 : ℝ → ℝ.
- (ii)μ((X − b+) ≥ μ((Y − b+) for any b ∈ ℝ.
- (iii)AVaR𝒫, λ(X) ≥ AVaR𝒫, λ(Y) for any λ ∈ (0, 1).
- (iv)g ∘ μ(X) ≥ g ∘ μ(Y) for all concave distortion functions g.
Let μ be a capacity induced by a family of probability measures 𝒫, which is determined by the sublunar expectation 𝔼. Let X, Y ∈ 𝓗. The following statements are equivalent.
- (i)μ(𝜙(X)) ≥ μ(𝜙(Y)) for all increasing function 𝜙 : ℝ → ℝ.
- (ii)Gμ, X(x) ≥ Gμ, Y(x), ∀x ∈ ℝ.
- (iii)VaR𝒫, λ(X) ≥ VaR𝒫, λ(Y), for any λ ∈ (0, 1).
- (iv)g ∘ μ(X) ≥ g ∘ μ (Y) for all distortion functions g.
4 Conclusions
This paper considers the uncertainty orders on the sublinear expectation space from two different viewpoints. It is worth noting that the sublinear expectation does not equal to the Choquet integral generally, where the capacity is induced by sublinear expectation. The readers can refer to [25] and [26] for more details. We only consider some special distributions in the first viewpoint, and other plausible formulation leaves to a future study.
The authors are very grateful to the editor and an anonymous referee for several constructive and insightful comments on how to improve the paper. This work was supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (11371362), the Natural Science Foundation of Jiangsu Province (BK20150167).
References
- [1]↑
Artzner, P., Delbaen, F., Eber, J. M. and Heath, D. Coherent measures of risk. Math. Financ., 9, 203-228, 1999.
- [2]↑
Delbaen, F. Coherent risk measures on general probability spaces. In: Sandmann, K., Schonbucher, P.J. (Eds.), Advances in Finance Stochastics: Essays in Honour of Dieter Sondermann. Springer, New York, pp. 1-37, 2002.
- [4]↑
Peng, S. BSDE and related g-expectation. Pitman Research Notes in Mathematics Series, No. 364, N. El Karoui and L. Mazliak (eds.), 141-159, 1997.
- [5]
Peng, S. G-Expectation, G-Brownian Motion and Related Stochastic Calculus of Itô’s type. In Stochastic Analysis and Applications, Able Symposium, Abel Symposia 2, Benth et al. (eds.), Springer-Verlag, 541-567, 2006.
- [6]↑
Peng, S. G-Brownian motion and dynamic risk measure under volatility uncertainty. In arXiv:0711.2834v1 [math.PR], 2007.
- [7]
Peng, S. Multi-dimensional G-Brownian motion and related stochastic calculus under G-expectation. Stoch. Proc. Appl., 118(12), 2223-2253, 2008.
- [8]↑
Peng, S. Nonlinear Expectations and Stochastic Calculus under Uncertainty with Robust Central Limit Theorem and G-Brownian Motion. In arXiv:1002.4546v1 [math.PR], 2010.
- [9]
He, K., Hu, M., and Chen, Z. The relationship between risk measures and choquet expectations in the framework of g-expectations. Stat. Probabil. Lett., 79, 508-512, 2009,
- [10]↑
Jiang, L. Convexity, Translation Invariance and Subadditivity for g-Expectations and Related Risk Measures. Ann. Appl. Probab., 18, 1245-1258, 2008.
- [11]↑
von Neumann, J., Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. 2nd edn. Princeton University Press, 1947.
- [12]↑
Föllmer, H. and Schied, A. Stochastic Finance, An Introduction in Discrete Time. Welter de Gruyter, 2004.
- [14]↑
Grigorova, M. Stochastic orderings with respect to a capacity and an application to a financial optimization problem. HAL : hal-00614716, version 1, 2011.
- [15]↑
Grigorova, M. Stochastic dominance with respect to a capacity and risk measures. HaL: hal-00639667, version 1, 2011.
- [16]↑
Müller, A. Stochastic ordering of multivariate normal distributions. Ann. Inst. Statist. Math., 53 (3), 567-575, 2001.
- [17]↑
Hu, M. Explicit solutions of the G-heat equation for a class of initial conditions. Nonlinear Analysis, 75, 6588-6595, 2012.
- [21]↑
Wang, S. Premium calculation by transforming the layer premium density. ASTIN Bulletin, 26, 71-92, 1996.
- [22]↑
Dhaene, J., Vanduffel, S., Goovaerts, M.J., Kaas, R., Tang, Q., Vyncke, D. Risk measures and comotononicity: A review. Stochastic Models 22, 573-606, 2002.
- [23]↑
Kervarec, M., 2008. Etude des modeles non domines en mathematiques financieres. These de Doctorat en Mathematiques, Universite dEvry
- [24]↑
Föllmer, H., Knispel, T. Entropic risk measures: coherence vs. convexity, model ambiguity, and robust large deviations. Stochastics and Dynamics, 11(2-3), 333-351, 2011.
- [25]↑
Huber, P., Strassen, V. Minimax tests the Neyman-Pearson lemma for capacity. A. Statist. 1, 252-263, 1973.
- [26]↑
Chen, Z., Chen, T., Matt, D. Choquet expectation and Peng’s g-expectation. The Annals of Probability, 33, 1179-1199, 2005.